|
![]() ![]() ![]() |
|
Thales
(THAY-leez) is usually thought
of as the "Father" of Western philosophy. For reasons not known to
us (until the time of Plato in the late 400s BC we have no actual writings
of the earliest Greek philosophers, only bits and pieces about them told
by others – others not necessarily sympathetic observers!), Thales was
not content with the idea that things are the way they are because of the
doings of the gods.
Thales was well versed in the scientific learning of the East – and probably traveled to Egypt to study the mathematics, geometry and astronomy of the Egyptians. He put his learning to work as a military engineer – and was fabled for his scientific genius. He predicted a solar eclipse, measured the shadows of objects (from pyramids to ships) to estimate their distances or locations. It is reported of him that he even diverted a river in order to better position the Milesian army against an enemy city. But it is in the area of philosophical thought that Thales is best remembered. Thales was interested in discovering, through the process of rational enquiry, the essence or substance of all matter. He looked out on the world as a by-product of some material substance – a single substance which by its own makeup or inner mechanics could bring into being all other things. For him that single substance was water. Perhaps such a conclusion was inevitable for one who grew up near the sea and who undoubtedly often watched the power of the clouds above and the waves below during a tempest. But remember also that the ancient world widely shared the view that creation emerged from a watery void. In any
case, it is important to understand
how significant his probing into the essence of things was. He may
not have got the right answers (though he was not really so far off in
his view of water as the original substance) – but he was asking what modern
science even today considers the right questions.
Thus in ascribing the dynamics of the universe to water as the formative substance, rather than to the gods as the formative powers, he became our first known "materialist" or "secularist. |
|
Thales' rational inquiry was taken up by Anaximander (ann-AKS-imander), reported by some to have been a student of Thales.' In many ways he continued the intellectual tradition of Thales, becoming enlightened in a number of the sciences of the day. He is reported to have written down his vast learning on a wide range of subjects – though we have today only a small portion of his work, Concerning Nature. We know also however that Anaximander objected to Thales' theory – on the basis that water could not be the formative substance of life and yet at the same time one of its end products. Anaximander speculated that the original substance of the universe was some kind of primal, formless material which is found infinitely throughout creation – the material source of all created things (including water) and the material into which the universe will eventually return. He also speculated that the world was the result of a process of moving forces, a process that holds the universe steadily on its course – and leads it into the future. He saw this process as one ultimately of moving all things to maintain or restore a primal balance, one in which the multitude of forces in the cosmos work in the long run to counterbalance each in order to produce a basic harmony. Hot balances cold, dry balances wet, etc. to provide a cosmic harmony. But the actual dynamic of life involves a separation of these opposites – a falling into their particulars (an act of cosmic ‘injustice’), from which then a basic urge toward harmony (a return toward ‘justice’) moves them forward. This is the cause of motion or action in the universe: the urge to reharmonize. He speculated that the earth was a solid object hanging in a fixed position in the emptiness of space because it was equidistant from everything else, the very center of balance of all the forces in the universe. He might have viewed the world therefore as a ball or globe at the very center of the universe, but the flatness of the earth seemed so self evident that he supposed instead that the earth might be a huge cylinder, like a drum. We move around on one of the flat sides of the drum, held in place by balancing forces arising from the other flat side of the drum. He also looked at his universe in
terms of its natural history: things as we know them today are a
result of this process or urge of things to come into balance. This
urge toward balance moves all things forward through time from one state
or condition to the next, producing an ‘evolution’ of all things
– from simpler into more complex forms. Human beings evolved
rather more recently in the long natural history of the cosmos.
Anaximander really was raising the ‘teleological’ issue in philosophy. He looked at creation, at life, from the point of view of where did things (material things) come from, why were they here, and what was their destiny. He too rejected the notion that this was all a matter of the doings of the gods on Olympus. And he too, like Thales, surmised that the vital forces of life are somehow contained within the ‘stuff’ of life itself. He, like Thales, was a materialist – and also an evolutionist! |
|
Anaximenes (anak-SI-muneez) was reportedly a pupil of Anaximander's and the third in the trio of great Milesian philosophers. He rejected most of Anaximander's theories about the world and the surrounding universe. He felt that it was self-evident that the world was a flat object, not a cylinder, and he rejected the idea of the earth just hanging in a void of space. Like Thales, Anaximenes looked to a less mysterious source of all things, to a primary material substance foundational to all things, one more readily present in our observable world. Anaximenes concluded that the primal substance of life was air or mist (pneuma) – an invisible substance that filled all the universe. It could be both the source of all things, and yet one of the created things itself – because of its power to change form. Here too, it was probably natural for Anaximenes to accord air the honor of being the primal substance or underlying material of all things. Greeks commonly understood air to be the ‘breath’ or ‘spirit’ (also pneuma) of life, the source of the soul, and so it was logical to think that air might be the primal substance of all things, the soul or spirit of all life. In any case, he argued that through a process of becoming more or less dense, air could change form. Thus fire was air in its most rarified form. The natural progress from there as air thickened was: wind, clouds, water, earth, and stone. Also, the soul quality of air (as the Greeks understood it) could explain movement, events, life itself. All in all, Anaximines' theory of the substance of life seems more complete than his Milesian predecessors. It was truly a great intellectual accomplishment – though being founded on a faulty premise, we find it interesting only for its methodology and not for its conclusions. |