LIFE OF EPICURUS
I. Epicurus was an Athenian, and the son of Neocles and
Chærestrate, of the burgh of Gargettus, and of the family of
the Philaidæ, as Metrodorus tells us in his treatise on Nobility
of Birth. Some writers, and among them Heraclides, in his
Abridgment of Sotion, say, that as the Athenians had colonised
Samos, he was brought up there, and came to Athens in
his eighteenth year, while Xenocrates was president of the
Academy, and Aristotle at Chalcis. But after the death of
Alexander, the Macedonian, when the Athenians were driven
out of Samos by Perdiccas, Epicurus went to Colophon to
his father.
II. And when he had spent some time there, and collected
some disciples, he again returned to Athens, in the time of
Anaxicrates, and for some time studied philosophy, mingling
with the rest of the philosophers; but subsequently, he some
how or other established the school which was called after his
name; and he used to say, that he began to study philosophy,
when he was fourteen years of age; but Apollodorus, the
Epicurean, in the first book of his account of the life of
Epicurus, says, that he came to the study of philosophy,
having conceived a great contempt for the grammarians,
because they could not explain to him the statements in
Hesiod respecting Chaos.
But Hermippus tells us, that he himself was a teacher of
grammar, and that afterwards, having met with the books of
Democritus, he applied himself with zeal to philosophy, on
which account Timon says of him:—
The last of all the natural philosophers,
And the most shameless too, did come from Samos,
A grammar teacher, and the most ill-bred
And most unmanageable of mankind.
And he had for his companions in his philosophical studies,
his three brothers, Neocles, Chæredemus, and Aristobulus,
who were excited by his exhortations, as Philodemus, the
Epicurean, relates in the tenth book of the Classification of
Philosophers. He had also a slave, whose name was Mus, as
Myronianus tells us in his Similar Historical Chapters.
III. But Diotimus, the Stoic, was very hostile to him, and
calumniated him in a most bitter manner, publishing fifty
obscene letters, and attributing them to Epicurus, and also
giving him the credit of the letters, which generally go under
the name of Chrysippus. And Posidonius, the Stoic, and
Nicolaus, and Sotion, in the twelfth of these books, which are
entitled the Refutations of Diocles, of which there are
altogether twenty-four volumes, and Dionysius, of Halicarnassus,
have also attacked him with great severity; for they
say that he used to accompany his mother when she went
about the small cottages, performing purifications, and that
he used to read the formula, and that he used also to keep a
school with his father at very low terms. Also, that he, as
well as one of his brothers, was a most profligate man in
his morals, and that he used to live with Leontium, the
courtesan. Moreover, that he claimed the books of Democritus
on Atoms, and that of Aristippus on Pleasure, as his
own; and that he was not a legitimate citizen; and this last
fact is asserted also by Timocrates, and by Herodotus, in his
treatise on the Youth of Epicurus.
They also say that he used to flatter Mithras, the steward
of Lysimachus, in a disgraceful manner, calling him in his
letters Pæan, and King; and also that he flattered Idomeneus,
and Herodotus, and Timocrates who had revealed all his secret
practices, and that he flattered them on this very account.
And in his letters to Leontium, he says, “O king Apollo, my
dear Leontium, what transports of joy did I feel when I read
your charming letter.” And to Themista, the wife of Leonteus,
he writes, “I am ready and prepared, if you do not come to
me, to roll myself to wherever you and Themista invite
me.” And he addresses Pythocles, a beautiful youth, thus,
“I will sit quiet,” says he, “awaiting your longed for and
god-like approach.” And at another time, writing to Themista,
he says, “That he had determined to make his way with her,”
as Theodorus tells us in the fourth book of his treatises
against Epicurus.
He also wrote to many other courtesans, and especially to
Leontium, with whom Metrodorus also was in love. And in
his treatise on the Chief Good, he writes thus, “For I do not
know what I can consider good, if I put out of sight the
pleasures which arise from favours, and those which are
derived from amatory pleasures, and from music, and from the
contemplation of beauty.” And in his letter to Pythocles, he
writes, “And, my dear boy, avoid all sorts of education.”
Epictetus also attacks him as a most debauched man, and
reproaches him most vehemently, and so does Timocrates, the
brother of Metrodorus, in his treatise entitled the Merry
Guests, and this Timocrates had been a disciple in his school,
though he afterwards abandoned it; and he says that he used
to vomit twice a day, in consequence of his intemperance; and
that he himself had great difficulty in escaping from this nocturnal
philosophy, and that mystic kind of re-union. He also
accuses Epicurus of shameful ignorance in his reasoning, and
still more especially in all matters relating to the conduct of
life. And says that he was in a pitiable state of health, so
that he could not for many years rise up from his sofa; and
that he used to spend a minæ a day on his eating, as he
himself states in his letter to Leontium, and in that to the
philosophers at Mitylene. He also says that many courtesans
used to live with him and Metrodorus; and among them
Marmarium, and Hedea, and Erotium, and Nicidium.
IV. And in the thirty-seven books which he wrote about
natural philosophy, they say that he says a great many things
of the same kind over and over again, and that in them he
writes in contradiction of other philosophers, and especially of
Nausiphanes, and speaks as follows, word for word: “But if
any one else ever was afflicted in such a manner, then certainly
this man had a continual labour, striving to bring forth the
sophistical boastfulness of his mouth, like many other slaves.”
And Epicurus also speaks of Nausiphanes in his letters, in the
following terms: “These things led him on to such arrogance
of mind, that he abused me and called me a schoolmaster.”
He used also to call him Lungs, and Blockhead, and Humbug,
and Fornicator. And he used to call Plato’s followers Flatterers
of Dionysius, but Plato himself he called Golden.
Aristotle he called a debauchee and a glutton, saying that he
joined the army after he had squandered his patrimony, and
sold drugs. He used also to call Protagoras a porter, and the
secretary of Democritus, and to say that he taught boys their
letters in the streets. Heraclitus, he called a disturber; Democritus,
he nicknamed Lerocritus; and Antidorus, Sænidorus;
the Cynics he called enemies of Greece; and the Dialecticians
he charged with being eaten up with envy. Pyrrho, he said,
was ignorant and unlearned.
V. But these men who say this are all wrong, for there are
plenty of witnesses of the unsurpassable kindness of the man
to every body; both his own country which honoured him with
brazen statues, and his friends who were so numerous that they
could not be contained in whole cities; and all his acquaintances
who were bound to him by nothing but the charms of his
doctrine, none of whom ever deserted him, except Metrodorus,
the son of Stratoniceus, who went over to Carneades,
probably because he was not able to bear with equanimity the
unapproachable excellence of Epicurus. Also, the perpetual
succession of his school, which, when every other school decayed,
continued without any falling off, and produced a countless
number of philosophers, succeeding one another without any
interruption. We may also speak here of his gratitude towards
his parents, and his beneficence to his brothers, and his
gentleness to his servants (as is plain from his will, and from
the fact too, that they united with him in his philosophical
studies, and the most eminent of them was the one whom I
have mentioned already, named Mus); and his universal
philanthropy towards all men.
His piety towards the Gods, and his affection for his country
was quite unspeakable; though, from an excess of modesty, he
avoided affairs of state. And though he lived when very
difficult times oppressed Greece, he still remained in his
own country, only going two or three times across to Ionia
to see his friends, who used to throng to him from all quarters,
and to live with him in his garden, as we are told by Apollodorus.
(This garden he bought for eighty minæ.)
VI. And Diocles, in the third book of his Excursion, says
that they all lived in the most simple and economical manner;
“They were content,” says he, “with a small cup of light
wine, and all the rest of their drink was water.” He also
tells us that Epicurus would not allow his followers to throw
their property into a common stock, as Pythagoras did, who
said that the possessions of friends were held in common.
For he said that such a doctrine as that was suited rather
for those who distrusted one another; and that those who
distrusted one another were not friends. But he himself
in his letters, says that he is content with water and plain
bread, and adds, “Send me some Cytherean cheese, that if I
wish to have a feast, I may have the means.” This was the
real character of the man who laid down the doctrine that
pleasure was the chief good; whom Athenæus thus mentions
in an epigram:—
O men, you labour for pernicious ends;
And out of eager avarice, begin
Quarrels and wars. And yet the wealth of nature
Fixes a narrow limit for desires,
Though empty judgment is insatiable.
This lesson the wise child of Neocles
Had learnt by heart, instructed by the Muses,
Or at the sacred shrine of Delphi’s God.
And as we advance further, we shall learn this fact from his
dogmas, and his apophthegms.
VII. Of all the ancient philosophers he was, as we are told
by Diocles, most attached to Anaxagoras (although in some
points he argued against him); and to Archelaus, the master
of Socrates. And he used, Diocles adds, to accustom his pupils
to preserve his writings in their memory. Apollodorus, in his
Chronicles, asserts that he was a pupil of Nausiphanes, and
Praxiphanes; but he himself does not mention this; but says
in his letter to Euridicus, that he had been his own instructor.
He also agreed with Hermarchus in not admitting that
Leucippus deserved to be called a philosopher; though some
authors, among whom is Apollodorus, speak of him as the
master of Democritus. Demetrius, the Magnesian, says that
he was a pupil of Xenocrates also.
VIII. He uses in his works plain language with respect to
anything he is speaking of, for which Aristophanes, the grammarian,
blames him, on the ground of that style being vulgar.
But he was such an admirer of perspicuity, that even in his
treatise on Rhetoric, he aims at and recommends nothing but
clearness of expression. And in his letters, instead of the
usual civil expressions, “Greeting,” “Farewell,” and so on,
he substitutes, “May you act well,” “May you live virtuously,”
and expressions of that sort. Some of his biographers assert
that it was he who composed the treatise entitled the Canon,
in imitation of the Tripod of Nausiphanes, whose pupil they
say that he was, and add that he was also a pupil of Pamphilus,
the Platonist, at Samos.
IX. They further tell us that he began to study philosophy
at twelve years of age, and that he presided over his school
thirty-two years. And he was born as we are told by Apollodorus,
in his Chronicles, in the third year of the hundred and
ninth olympiad, in the archonship of Sosigenes, on the seventh
day of the month Gamelion, seven years after the death of
Plato. And when he was thirty-two years of age, he first set
up his school at Mitylene, and after that at Lampsacus; and
when he had spent five years in these two cities, he came to
Athens; and he died there in the second year of the hundred
and twenty-seventh olympiad, in the archonship of Pytharatus,
when he had lived seventy-two years. And Hermarchus, the
son of Agemarchus, and a citizen of Mitylene, succeeded him
in his school.
He died of the stone, as Hermarchus mentions in his letters,
after having been ill a fortnight; and at the end of the fortnight,
Hermippus says that he went into a brazen bath,
properly tempered with warm water, and asked for a cup of
pure wine and drank it; and having recommended his friends
to remember his doctrines, he expired. And there is an
epigram of ours on him, couched in the following language:—
Now, fare-ye-well, remember all my words;
This was the dying charge of Epicurus:
Then to the bath he went, and drank some wine,
And sank beneath the cold embrace of Pluto.
Such was the life of the man, and such was his death.
X. And he made his will in the following terms:—
“According to this my will, I give all my possessions to
Amynomachus, of Bate, the son of Philocrates, and to Timocrates,
of Potamos, the son of Demetrius; according to the
deed of gift to each, which is deposited in the temple of
Cybele; on condition that they make over my garden and all
that is attached to it to Hermarchus, of Mitylene, the son of
Agemarchus; and to those who study philosophy with him,
and to whomsoever Hermarchus leaves as his successors in his
school, that they may abide and dwell in it, in the study and
practice of philosophy; and I give it also to all those who
philosophize according to my doctrines, that they may, to the
best of their ability, maintain my school which exists in my
garden, in concert with Amynomachus and Timocrates; and
I enjoin their heirs to do the same in the most perfect and
secure manner that they can; so that they also may maintain
my garden, as those also shall to whom my immediate successors
hand it down. As for the house in Melita, that Amynomachus
and Timocrates shall allow Hermarchus that he may
live in it during his life, together with all his companions in
philosophy.
“Out of the income which is derived from that property,
which is here bequeathed by me to Amynomachus and Timocrates,
I will that they, consulting with Hermarchus, shall
arrange in the best manner possible the offerings to the manes
in honour of the memory of my father, and mother, and
brothers, and myself, and that my birth-day may be kept as it
has been in the habit of being kept, on the tenth day of the
month Gamelion; and that the re-union of all the philosophers
of our school, established in honour of Metrodorus and myself,
may take place on the twentieth day of every month. They
shall also celebrate, as I have been in the habit of doing
myself, the day consecrated to my brothers, in the month
Poseideon; and the day consecrated to the memory of
Polyænus, in the month Metageitnion.
“Amynomachus and Timocrates, shall be the guardians of
Epicurus, the son of Metrodorus, and of the son of Polyænus,
as long as they study philosophy under, and live with, Hermarchus.
In the same way also, they shall be the guardians of
the daughter of Metrodorus, and when she is of marriageable
age, they shall give her to whomsoever Hermarchus shall select
of his companions in philosophy, provided she is well behaved
and obedient to Hermarchus. And Amynomachus and Timocrates
shall, out of my income, give them such a sum for their
support as shall appear sufficient year by year, after due
consultation with Hermarchus. And they shall associate
Hermarchus with themselves in the management of my
revenues, in order that everything may be done with the
approval of that man who has grown old with me in the study
of philosophy, and who is now left as the president of all those
who have studied philosophy with us. And as for the dowry
for the girl when she is come to marriageable age, let Amynomachus
and Timocrates arrange that, taking for the purpose
such a sum from my property as shall seem to them, in conjunction
with Hermarchus, to be reasonable. And let them
also take care of Nicanor, as we ourselves have done; in order
that all those who have studied philosophy with us, and who
have assisted us with their means, and who have shown great
friendship for us, and who have chosen to grow old with us in
the study of philosophy, may never be in want of anything as
far as our power to prevent it may extend.
“I further enjoin them to give all my books to Hermarchus;
and, if anything should happen to Hermarchus before the
children of Metrodorus are grown up, then I desire that
Amynomachus and Timocrates, shall take care that, provided
they are well behaved, they shall have everything that is
necessary for them, as far as the estate which I leave behind
me shall allow such things to be furnished to them. And the
same men shall also take care of everything else that I have
enjoined; so that it may all be fulfilled, as far as the case may
permit.
“Of my slaves, I hereby emancipate Mus, and Nicias, and
Lycon: I also give Phædrium her freedom.”
And when he was at the point of death, he wrote the
following letter to Idomeneus:—
“We have written this letter to you on a happy day to us,
which is also the last day of our life. For strangury has
attacked me, and also a dysentery, so violent that nothing
can be added to the violence of my sufferings. But the
cheerfulness of my mind, which arises from the recollection of
all my philosophical contemplations, counterbalances all these
afflictions. And I beg you to take care of the children of
Metrodorus, in a manner worthy of the devotion shown by the
youth to me, and to philosophy.”
Such then as I have given it, was his will.
XI. He had a great number of pupils, of whom the most
eminent were Metrodorus, the Athenian, and Timocrates, and
Sandes, of Lampsacus; who, from the time that he first became
acquainted with him, never left him, except once when he went
home for six months; after which he returned to him. And
he was a virtuous man in every respect, as Epicurus tells us in
his Fundamental Principles. And he also bears witness to
his virtue in the third book of his Timocrates. And being a
man of this character, he gave his sister Batis in marriage to
Idomeneus; and he himself had Leontium, the Attic courtesan,
for his concubine. He was very unmoved at all disturbances,
and even at death; as Epicurus tells us, in the first book of
his Metrodorus. He is said to have died seven years before
Epicurus himself, in the fifty-third year of his age. And
Epicurus himself, in the will which I have given above, gives
many charges about the guardianship of his children, showing
by this that he had been dead some time. He also had a
brother whom I have mentioned before, of the name of Timocrates,
a trifling, silly man.
The writings of Metrodorus are these. Three books addressed
to the Physicians; one essay on the Sensations; one addressed
to Timocrates; one on Magnanimity; one on the Illness of
Epicurus; one addressed to the Dialecticians; one against the
Nine Sophists; one on the Road to Wisdom; one on Change;
one on Riches; one against Democritus; one on Nobility of
Birth.
XII. Likewise Polyænus, of Lampsacus, the son of Athenodorus,
was a man of mild and friendly manners, as Philodemus
particularly assures us.
XIII. And his successor was Hermarchus, of Mitylene, the
son of Agemarchus, a poor man; and his favourite pursuit was
rhetoric. And the following excellent works of his are extant.
Twenty-two books of letters about Empedocles; an essay on
Mathematics; A treatise against Plato; another against
Aristotle. And he died of paralysis, being a most eminent
man.
XIV. There was also Leonteus, of Lampsacus, and his wife
Themista, to whom Epicurus wrote.
XV. There were also Colotes and Idomeneus; and these
also were natives of Lampsacus. And among the most eminent
philosophers of the school of Epicurus, were Polystratus, who
succeeded Hermarchus, and Dionysius who succeeded him, and
Basilides who succeeded him. Likewise Apollodorus, who was
nicknamed the tyrant of the gardens (κηποτύραννος), was a very
eminent man, and wrote more than four hundred books. And
there were the two Ptolemies of Alexandria, Ptolemy the
Black, and Ptolemy the Fair. And Zeno, of Sidon, a pupil
of Apollodorus, a very voluminous author; and Demetrius,
who was surnamed the Lacedæmonian; and Diogenes, of
Tarsus, who wrote the Select Dialogues; and Orion, and
others whom the genuine Epicureans call Sophists.
XVI. There were also three other persons of the name of
Epicurus; first, the son of Leonteus and Themista; secondly,
a native of Magnesia; and lastly, a Gladiator.
XVII. And Epicurus was a most voluminous author,
exceeding all men in the number of his books; for there are
more than three hundred volumes of them; and in the whole
of them there is not one citation from other sources, but they
are filled wholly with the sentiments of Epicurus himself. In
the quantity of his writings he was rivalled by Chrysippus, as
Carneades asserts, who calls him a parasite of the books of
Epicurus; for if ever this latter wrote anything, Chrysippus
immediately set his heart on writing a book of equal size; and
in this way he often wrote the same thing over again; putting
down whatever came into his head; and he published it all
without any corrections, by reason of his haste. And he quotes
such numbers of testimonies from other authors, that his
books are entirely filled with them alone; as one may find
also in the works of Aristotle and Zeno.
Such then, and so numerous are the works of Epicurus;
the chief of which are the following. Thirty-seven treatises
on Natural Philosophy; one on Atoms, and the Vacuum;
one on Love; an abridgment of the Arguments employed
against the Natural Philosophers; Doubts in Contradiction of
the Doctrines of the Megarians; Fundamental Propositions;
a treatise on Choice and Avoidance; another on the Chief
Good; another on the Criterion, called also the Canon;
the Chæredemus, a treatise on the Gods; one on Piety;
the Hegesianax; four essays on Lives; one on Just Dealing;
the Neocles; one essay addressed to Themista; the Banquet;
the Eurylochus; one essay addressed to Metrodorus; one
on Seeing; one on the Angle in an Atom; one on Touch;
one on Fate; Opinions on the Passions; one treatise
addressed to Timocrates; Prognostics; Exhortations; a
treatise on Spectres; one on Perceptions; the Aristobulus;
an essay on Music; one on Justice and the other Virtues;
one on Gifts and Gratitude; the Polymedes; the Timocrates,
a treatise in three books; the Metrodorus, in five books;
the Antidorus, in two books; Opinions about the South
Winds; a treatise addressed to Mithras; the Callistolas;
an essay on Kingly Power; the Anaximenes; Letters.
XVIII. And I will endeavour to give an abridgment of
the doctrines contained in these works, as it may be agreeable,
quoting three letters of his, in which he has made a sort of
epitome of all his philosophy. I will also give his fundamental
and peculiar opinions, and any apophthegms which he uttered
which appear worthy of being selected. So that you may be
thoroughly acquainted with the man, and may also judge that
I understand him.
Now the first letter is one that he wrote to Herodotus, on
the subject of Natural Philosophy; the second is one that he
wrote to Pythocles, which is about the Heavenly Bodies;
the third is addressed to Menœceus, and in that there are contained
the discussions about lives.
We must now begin with the first, after having said a little
by way of preface concerning the divisions of philosophy which
he adopted.
XIX. Now he divides philosophy into three parts. The
canonical, the physical, and the ethical. The canonical, which
serves as an introduction to science, is contained in the single
treatise which is called the Canon. The physical embraces
the whole range of speculation on subjects of natural philosophy,
and is contained in the thirty-seven books on nature,
and in the letters again it is discussed in an elementary manner.
The ethical contains the discussions on Choice and Avoidance;
and is comprised in the books about lives, and in some of the
Letters, and in the treatise on the Chief Good. Accordingly,
most people are in the habit of combining the canonical division
with the physical; and then they designate the whole
under the names of the criterion of the truth, and a discussion
on principles, and elements. And they say that the physical
division is conversant about production, and destruction, and
nature; and that the ethical division has reference to the
objects of choice and avoidance, and lives, and the chief good
of mankind.
XX. Dialectics they wholly reject as superfluous. For they
say that the correspondence of words with things is sufficient
for the natural philosopher, so as to enable him to advance
with certainty in the study of nature.
Now, in the Canon, Epicurus says that the criteria of truth
are the senses, and the preconceptions, and the passions. But
the Epicureans, in general, add also the perceptive impressions
of the intellect. And he says the same thing in his Abridgment,
which he addresses to Herodotus, and also in his Fundamental
Principles. For, says he, the senses are devoid of
reason, nor are they capable of receiving any impressions of
memory. For they are not by themselves the cause of any
motion, and when they have received any impression from any
external cause, then they can add nothing to it, nor can they
subtract anything from it. Moreover, they are out of the
reach of any control; for one sensation cannot judge of another
which resembles itself; for they have all an equal value. Nor
can one judge of another which is different from itself; since
their objects are not identical. In a word, one sensation
cannot control another, since the effects of all of them influence
us equally. Again, the reason cannot pronounce on the senses;
for we have already said that all reasoning has the senses for
its foundation. Reality and the evidence of sensation establish
the certainty of the senses; for the impressions of sight and
hearing are just as real, just as evident, as pain.
It follows from these considerations that we ought to judge
of things which are obscure by their analogy to those which
we perceive directly. In fact, every notion proceeds from the
senses, either directly, or in consequence of some analogy, or
proportion, or combination. Reasoning having always a share
in these last operations. The visions of insanity and of sleep
have a real object, for they act upon us; and that which
has no reality can produce no action.
XXI. By preconception, the Epicureans mean a sort of
comprehension as it were, or right opinion, or notion, or general
idea which exists in us; or, in other words, the recollection
of an external object often perceived anteriorly. Such for
instance, is this idea: “Man is a being of such and such a
nature.” At the same moment that we utter the word man,
we conceive the figure of a man, in virtue of a preconception
which we owe to the preceding operations of the senses.
Therefore, the first notion which each word awakens in us is
a correct one; in fact, we could not seek for anything if we
had not previously some notion of it. To enable us to affirm
that what we see at a distance is a horse or an ox, we must
have some preconception in our minds which makes us acquainted
with the form of a horse and an ox. We could not
give names to things, if we had not a preliminary notion of
what the things were.
XXII. These preconceptions then furnish us with certainty.
And with respect to judgments, their certainty depends on
our referring them to some previous notion, of itself certain,
in virtue of which we affirm such and such a judgment; for
instance, “How do we know whether this thing is a man?”
The Epicureans call opinion (δόξα) also supposition (ὑπόληψις).
And say that it is at times true, and at times false; for that,
if it is supported by testimony, and not contradicted by testimony,
then it is true; but if it is not supported by testimony,
and is contradicted by testimony, then it is false. On which
account they have introduced the expression of “waiting,” as if,
before pronouncing that a thing seen is a tower, we must wait
till we come near, and learn what it looks like when we are
near it.
XXIII. They say that there are two passions, pleasure and
pain, which affect everything alive. And that the one is
natural, and the other foreign to our nature; with reference to
which all objects of choice and avoidance are judged of. They
say also, that there are two kinds of investigation; the one
about facts, the other about mere words. And this is as far as
an elementary sketch can go—their doctrine about division,
and about the criterion.
XXIV. Let us now go to the letter:—
EPICURUS TO HERODOTUS, WISHING HE MAY DO WELL
“For those, O Herodotus, who are not able accurately to
comprehend all the things which I have written about nature,
nor to investigate those larger books which I have composed on
the subject, I have made an abridgment of the whole discussion
on this question, as far as I thought sufficient to enable
them to recollect accurately the most fundamental points;
that so, on all grave occasions, they might be able to assist
themselves on the most important and undeniable principles;
in proportion as they devoted themselves to speculations on
natural philosophy. And here it is necessary for those who
have made sufficient progress in their view of the general
question, to recollect the principles laid down as elements of
the whole discussion; for we have still greater need of a correct
notion of the whole, than we have even of an accurate understanding
of the details. We must, therefore, give preference
to the former knowledge, and lay up in our memory those
principles on which we may rest, in order to arrive at an
exact perception of things, and at a certain knowledge of
particular objects.
“Now one has arrived at that point when one has thoroughly
embraced the conceptions, and, if I may so express myself,
the most essential forms, and when one has impressed them
adequately on one’s senses. For this clear and precise knowledge
of the whole, taken together, necessarily facilitates one’s
particular perceptions, when one has brought one’s ideas back
to the elements and simple terms. In short, a veritable
synthesis, comprising the entire circle of the phænomena of
the universe, ought to be able to resume in itself, and in a few
words, all the particular facts which have been previously
studied. This method being useful even to those who are
already familiarised with the laws of the universe, I recommend
them, while still pursuing without intermission the
study of nature, which contributes more than anything else to
the tranquillity and happiness of life, to make a concise statement
or summary of their opinions.
“First of all, then, Herodotus, one must determine with
exactness the notion comprehended under each separate word,
in order to be able to refer to it, as to a certain criterion, the
conceptions which emanate from ourselves, the ulterior researches
and the difficulties; otherwise the judgment has no
foundation. One goes on from demonstration to demonstration
ad infinitum; or else one gains nothing beyond mere words.
In fact, it is absolutely necessary that in every word we should
perceive directly, and without the assistance of any demonstration,
the fundamental notion which it expresses, if we wish to
have any foundation to which we may refer our researches, our
difficulties, and our personal judgments, whatever in other
respects may be the criterion which we adopt, whether we take
as our standard the impressions produced on our senses, or
the actual impression in general; or whether we cling to the
idea by itself, or to any other criterion.
“We must also note carefully the impressions which we
receive in the presence of objects, in order to bring ourselves
back to that point in the circumstances in which it is necessary
to suspend the judgment, or even when the question
is about things, the evidence of which is not immediately perceived.
“When these foundations are once laid we may pass to the
study of those things, the evidence of which is not immediate.
And, first of all, we must admit that nothing can come of that
which does not exist; for, were the fact otherwise, then every
thing would be produced from everything, and there would be
no need of any seed. And if that which disappeared were so
absolutely destroyed as to become non-existent, then every
thing would soon perish, as the things with which they would
be dissolved would have no existence. But, in truth, the
universal whole always was such as it now is, and always
will be such. For there is nothing into which it can change;
for there is nothing beyond this universal whole which can
penetrate into it, and produce any change in it.”
(And Epicurus establishes the same principles at the
beginning of the great Abridgment; and in the first book
of his treatise on Nature.) “Now the universal whole is a
body; for our senses bear us witness in every case that bodies
have a real existence; and the evidence of the senses, as I
have said before, ought to be the rule of our reasonings about
everything which is not directly perceived. Otherwise, if that
which we call the vacuum, or space, or intangible nature, had
not a real existence, there would be nothing on which the
bodies could be contained, or across which they could move, as
we see that they really do move. Let us add to this reflection
that one cannot conceive, either in virtue of perception, or of
any analogy founded on perception, any general quality peculiar
to all beings which is not either an attribute, or an
accident of the body, or of the vacuum.”
(The same principles are laid down in the first, and fourteenth,
and fifteenth book of the treatise on Nature; and also
in the Great Abridgment.)
“Now, of bodies, some are combinations, and some the
elements out of which these combinations are formed. These
last are indivisible, and protected from every kind of transformation;
otherwise everything would be resolved into non-existence.
They exist by their own force, in the midst of the
dissolution of the combined bodies, being absolutely full, and
as such offering no handle for destruction to take hold of. It
follows, therefore, as a matter of absolute necessity, that the
principles of things must be corporeal, indivisible elements.
“The universe is infinite. For that which is finite has an
extreme, and that which has an extreme is looked at in relation
to something else. Consequently, that which has not an
extreme, has no boundary; and if it has no boundary, it must be
infinite, and not terminated by any limit. The universe then is
infinite, both with reference to the quantity of bodies of which
it is made up, and to the magnitude of the vacuum; for if
the vacuum were infinite, the bodies being finite, then, the
bodies would not be able to rest in any place; they would be
transported about, scattered across the infinite vacuum for
want of any power to steady themselves, or to keep one another
in their places by mutual repulsion. If, on the other hand,
the vacuum were finite, the bodies being infinite, then the
bodies clearly could never be contained in the vacuum.
“Again: the atoms which form the bodies, these full elements
from which the combined bodies come, and into which they
resolve themselves, assume an incalculable variety of forms,
for the numerous differences which the bodies present cannot
possibly result from an aggregate of the same forms. Each
variety of forms contains an infinity of atoms, but there is not
for that reason an infinity of atoms; it is only the number of
them which is beyond all calculation.”
(Epicurus adds, a little lower down, that divisibility, ad infinitum,
is impossible; for, says he, the only things which
change are the qualities; unless, indeed, one wishes to proceed
from division to division, till one arrives absolutely at
infinite littleness.)
“The atoms are in a continual state of motion.”
(He says, farther on, that they move with an equal rapidity
from all eternity, since the vacuum offers no more resistance
to the lightest than it does to the heaviest.)
“Among the atoms, some are separated by great distances,
others come very near to one another in the formation of combined
bodies, or at times are enveloped by others which are
combining; but in this latter case they, nevertheless, preserve
their own peculiar motion, thanks to the nature of the vacuum,
which separates the one from the other, and yet offers them no
resistance. The solidity which they possess causes them,
while knocking against one another, to re-act the one upon
the other; till at last the repeated shocks bring on the dissolution
of the combined body; and for all this there is no
external cause, the atoms and the vacuum being the only
causes.”
(He says, further on, that the atoms have no peculiar quality
of their own, except from magnitude and weight. As to colour,
he says in the twelfth book of his Principia, that it varies
according to the position of the atoms. Moreover, he does not
attribute to the atoms any kind of dimensions; and, accordingly,
no atom has ever been perceived by the senses; but this
expression, if people only recollect what is here said, will by
itself offer to the thoughts a sufficient image of the nature of
things.)
“But, again, the worlds also are infinite, whether they resemble
this one of ours or whether they are different from it.
For, as the atoms are, as to their number, infinite, as I have
proved above, they necessarily move about at immense distances;
for besides, this infinite multitude of atoms, of which
the world is formed, or by which it is produced, could not be
entirely absorbed by one single world, nor even by any worlds,
the number of which was limited, whether we suppose them
like this world of ours, or different from it. There is, therefore,
no fact inconsistent with an infinity of worlds.
“Moreover, there are images resembling, as far as their form
goes, the solid bodies which we see, but which differ materially
from them in the thinness of their substance. In fact it is not
impossible but that there may be in space some secretions of
this kind, and an aptitude to form surfaces without depth, and
of an extreme thinness; or else that from the solids there
may emanate some particles which preserve the connection, the
disposition, and the motion which they had in the body. I
give the name of images to these representations; and, indeed,
their movement through the vacuum taking place, without
meeting any obstacle or hindrance, perfects all imaginable
extent in an inconceivable moment of time; for it is the
meeting of obstacles, or the absence of obstacles, which produces
the rapidity or the slowness of their motion. At all
events, a body in motion does not find itself, at any moment
imaginable, in two places at the same time; that is quite
inconceivable. From whatever point of infinity it arrives at
some appreciable moment, and whatever may be the spot in
its course in which we perceive its motion, it has evidently
quitted that spot at the moment of our thought; for this
motion which, as we have admitted up to this point, encounters
no obstacle to its rapidity, is wholly in the same condition as
that the rapidity of which is diminished by the shock of some
resistance.
“It is useful, also, to retain this principle, and to know that
the images have an incomparable thinness; which fact indeed
is in no respect contradicted by sensible appearances. From
which it follows that their rapidity also is incomparable; for
they find everywhere an easy passage, and besides, their infinite
smallness causes them to experience no shock, or at all events
to experience but a very slight one, while an infinite multitude
of elements very soon encounter some resistance.
“One must not forget that the production of images is simultaneous
with the thought; for from the surface of the bodies
images of this kind are continually flowing off in an insensible
manner indeed, because they are immediately replaced.
They preserve for a long time the same disposition, and the
same arrangement that the atoms do in the solid body,
although, notwithstanding, their form may be sometimes
altered. The direct production of images in space is equally
instantaneous, because these images are only light substances
destitute of depth.
“But there are other manners in which natures of this kind
are produced; for there is nothing in all this which at all
contradicts the senses, if one only considers in what way the
senses are exercised, and if one is inclined to explain the
relation which is established between external objects and
ourselves. Also, one must admit that something passes from
external objects into us in order to produce in us sight and
the knowledge of forms; for it is difficult to conceive that
external objects can affect us through the medium of the air
which is between us and them, or by means of rays, whatever
emissions proceed from us to them, so as to give us an impression
of their form and colour. This phenomenon, on the
contrary, is perfectly explained, if we admit that certain images
of the same colour, of the same shape, and of a proportionate
magnitude pass from these objects to us, and so arrive at
being seen and comprehended. These images are animated
by an exceeding rapidity, and, as on the other side, the solid
object forming a compact mass, and comprising a vast quantity
of atoms, emits always the same quantity of particles, the
vision is continued, and only produces in us one single perception
which preserves always the same relation to the
object. Every conception, every sensible perception which
bears upon the form or the other attributes of these images, is
only the same form of the solid perceived directly, either in
virtue of a sort of actual and continued condensation of the
image, or in consequence of the traces which it has left in us.
“Error and false judgments always depend upon the supposition
that a preconceived idea will be confirmed, or at all
events will not be overturned, by evidence. Then, when it is
not confirmed, we form our judgment in virtue of a sort of
initiation of the thoughts connected, it is true with the perception,
and with a direct representation; but still connected
also with a conception peculiar to ourselves, which is the
parent of error. In fact the representations which intelligence
reflects like a mirror, whether one perceives them in a dream,
or by any other conceptions of the intellect, or of any other of
the criteria, can never resemble the objects that one calls real
and true, unless there were objects of this kind perceived
directly. And, on the other side, error could not be possible
if we did not receive some other motion also, a sort of initiative
of intelligence connected; it is true with direct representation,
but going beyond that representative. These conceptions
being connected with the direct perception which
produces the representation, but going beyond it, in consequence
of a motion peculiar to the individual thought, produces error
when it is not confirmed by evidence, or when it is contradicted
by evidence; but when it is confirmed, or when it is
not contradicted by evidence, then it produces truth.
“We must carefully preserve these principles in order not to
reject the authority of the faculties which perceive truth
directly; and not, on the other hand, to allow what is false to
be established with equal firmness, so as to throw everything
into confusion.
“Moreover, hearing is produced by some sort of current proceeding
from something that speaks, or sounds, or roars, or in
any manner causes any sort of audible circumstance. And this
current is diffused into small bodies resembling one another
in their parts; which, preserving not only some kind of relation
between one another, but even a sort of particular identity
with the object from which they emanate, puts us, very frequently,
into a communication of sentiments with this object,
or at least causes us to become aware of the existence of some
external circumstance. If these currents did not carry with
them some sort of sympathy, then there would be no such perception.
We must not therefore think that it is the air which
receives a certain form, under the action of the voice or of
some other sound. For it is utterly impossible that the
voice should act in this manner on the air. But the percussion
produced in us when we, by the utterance of a voice,
cause a disengagement of certain particles, constitutes a
current resembling a light whisper, and prepares an acoustic
feeling for us.
“We must admit that the case of smelling is the same as
that of hearing. There would be no sense of smell if there
did not emanate from most objects certain particles capable
of producing an impression on the smell. One class being
ill-suited to the organ, and consequently producing a disordered
state of it, the other being suited to it, and causing it no
distress.
“One must also allow, that the atoms possess no one of the
qualities of sensible objects, except form, weight, magnitude
and anything else is unavoidably inherent in form; in fact,
every quality is changeable, but the atoms are necessarily
unchangeable; for it is impossible but that in the dissolution
of combined bodies, there must be something which continues
solid and indestructible, of such a kind, that it will not
change either into what does not exist, or out of what does
not exist; but that it results either from a simple displacement
of parts, which is the most usual case, or from the
addition or subtraction of certain particles. It follows from
that, that that which does not admit of any change in itself,
is imperishable, participates in no respect in the nature of
changeable things, and in a word, has its dimensions and
forms immutably determined. And this is proved plainly
enough, because even in the transformations which take place
under our eyes, in consequence of the retrenchment of certain
parts, we can still recognise the form of these constituent
parts; while those qualities, which are not constituent parts,
do not remain like the form, but perish in the dissolution of
the combination. The attributes which we have indicated,
suffice to explain all the differences of combined bodies; for
we must inevitably leave something indestructible, lest everything
should resolve itself into non-existence.
“However, one must not believe that every kind of magnitude
exists in atoms, lest we find ourselves contradicted by
phænomena. But we must admit that there are atoms of
different magnitude, because, as that is the case, it is then
more easy to explain the impressions and sensations; at all
events, I repeat, it is not necessary for the purpose of explaining
the differences of the qualities, to attribute to atoms
every kind of magnitude.
“We must not suppose either, that an atom can become
visible to us; for, first of all, one does not see that that is the
case, and besides, one cannot even conceive, how an atom is
to become visible; besides, we must not believe, that in a
finite body there are particles of every sort, infinite in number;
consequently, one must not only reject the doctrine of infinite
divisibility in parcels smaller and smaller, lest we should
be reducing everything to nothing, and find ourselves forced to
admit, that in a mass composed of a crowd of elements, existence
can reduce itself to non-existence. But one cannot even
suppose that a finite object can be susceptible of transformations
ad infinitum, or even of transformation into smaller
objects than itself; for when once one has said that there are
in an object particles of every kind, infinite in number, there
is absolutely no means whatever of imagining that this object
can have only a finite magnitude; in fact, it is evident that
these particles, infinite in number, have some kind of dimension
or other, and whatever this dimension may be in other
respects, the objects which are composed of it will have an
infinite magnitude; in presenting forms which are determined,
and limits which are perceived by the senses, one conceives,
easily, without its being necessary to study this last
question directly, that this would be the consequence of the
contrary supposition, and that consequently, one must come to
look at every object as infinite.
“One must also admit, that the most minute particle perceptible
to the sense, is neither absolutely like the objects
which are susceptible of transformation, nor absolutely different
from them. It has some characteristics in common with
the object which admit of transformation, but it also differs
from them, inasmuch as it does not allow any distinct parts
to be discerned in it. When then, in virtue of these common
characteristics, and of this resemblance, we wish to form an
idea of the smallest particle perceptible by the senses, in
taking the objects which change for our terms of comparison,
it is necessary that we should seize on some characteristic
common to these different objects. In this way, we examine
them successively, from the first to the last, not by themselves,
nor as composed of parts in juxtaposition, but only in their
extent; in other words, we consider the magnitudes by themselves,
and in an abstract manner, inasmuch as they measure,
the greater a greater extent, and the smaller a smaller extent.
This analogy applies to the atom, as far as we consider it as
having the smallest dimensions possible. Evidently by its
minuteness, it differs from all sensible objects, still this
analogy is applicable to it; in a word, we establish by this
comparison, that the atom really has some extent, but we
exclude all considerable dimensions, for the sake of only
investing it with the smallest proportions.
“We must also admit, in taking for our guide, the reasoning
which discourses to us things which are invisible to the senses,
that the most minute magnitudes, those which are not compound
magnitudes, and which from the limit of sensible
extent, are the first measure of the other magnitudes which
are only called greater or less in their relation to the others.
For these relations which they maintain with these particles,
which are not subject to transformation, suffice to give them
this characteristic of first measure. But they cannot, like
atoms, combine themselves, and form compound bodies in
virtue of any motion belonging to themselves.
“Moreover, we must not say (while speaking of the infinite),
that such or such a point is the highest point of it, or the
lowest. For height and lowness must not be predicated of the
infinite. We know, in reality, that if, wishing to determine
the infinite, we conceive a point above our head, this point,
whatever it may be, will never appear to us to have the character
in question: otherwise, that which would be situated
above the point so conceived as the limit of the infinite, would
be at the same moment, and by virtue of its relation to the
same point, both high and low; and this is impossible to
imagine.
“It follows that thought can only conceive that one single
movement of transference, from low to high, ad infinitum;
and one single movement from high to low. From low to
high, when even the object in motion, going from us to the
places situated above our heads, meets ten thousand times with
the feet of those who are above us; and from high to low,
when in the same way it advances towards the heads of those
who are below us. For these two movements, looked at by
themselves and in their whole, are conceived as really opposed
the one to the other, in their progress towards the infinite.
“Moreover, all the atoms are necessarily animated by the
same rapidity, when they move across the vacuum, or when no
obstacle thwarts them. For why should heavy atoms have a
more rapid movement than those which are small and light,
since in no quarter do they encounter any obstacle? Why, on
the other hand, should the small atoms have a rapidity superior
to that of the large ones, since both the one and the other
find everywhere an easy passage, from the very moment that
no obstacle intervenes to thwart their movements? Movement
from low to high, horizontal movement to and fro, in
virtue of the reciprocal percussion of the atoms, movement
downwards, in virtue of their weight, will be all equal, for in
whatever sense the atom moves, it must have a movement as
rapid as the thought, till the moment when it is repelled, in
virtue of some external cause, or of its own proper weight, by
the shock of some object which resists it.
“Again, even in the compound bodies, one atom does not
move more rapidly than another. In fact, if one only looks
at the continued movement of an atom which takes place in
an indivisible moment of time, the briefest possible, they all
have a movement equally rapid. At the same time, an atom
has not, in any moment perceptible to the intelligence, a continued
movement in the same direction; but rather a series
of oscillating movements from which there results, in the last
analysis, a continued movement perceptible to the senses.
If then, one were to suppose, in virtue of a reasoning on
things invisible, that, in the intervals of time accessible to
thought, the atoms have a continued movement one would
deceive one’s self, for that which is conceived by the thought is
true as well as that which is directly perceived.
“Let us now return to the study of the affections, and of the
sensations; for this will be the best method of proving that
the soul is a bodily substance composed of slight particles,
diffused over all the members of the body, and presenting a
great analogy to a sort of spirit, having an admixture of heat,
resembling at one time one, and at another time the other of
those two principles. There exists in it a special part, endowed
with an extreme mobility, in consequence of the exceeding
slightness of the elements which compose it, and also in
reference to its more immediate sympathy with the rest of the
body. That it is which the faculties of the soul sufficiently
prove, and the passions, and the mobility of its nature, and
the thoughts, and, in a word, everything, the privation of which
is death. We must admit that it is in the soul most especially
that the principle of sensation resides. At the same time, it
would not possess this power if it were not enveloped by the
rest of the body which communicates it to it, and in its turn
receives it from it, but only in a certain measure; for there
are certain affections of the soul of which it is not capable.
“It is on that account that, when the soul departs, the body
is no longer possessed of sensation; for it has not this power,
(that of sensation namely) in itself; but, on the other hand,
this power can only manifest itself in the soul through the
medium of the body. The soul, reflecting the manifestations
which are accomplished in the substance which environs it,
realises in itself, in a virtue or power which belongs to it, the
sensible affections, and immediately communicates them to the
body in virtue of the reciprocal bonds of sympathy which unite
it to the body; that is the reason why the destruction of a part
of the body does not draw after it a cessation of all feeling in
the soul while it resides in the body, provided that the senses
still preserve some energy; although, nevertheless, the dissolution
of the corporeal covering, or even of any one of its
portions, may sometimes bring on with it the destruction of
the soul.
“The rest of the body, on the other hand, even when it
remains, either as a whole, or in any part, loses all feeling by
the dispersion of that aggregate of atoms, whatever it may be,
that forms the soul. When the entire combination of the body
is dissolved, then the soul too is dissolved, and ceases to retain
those faculties which were previously inherent in it, and especially
the power of motion; so that sensation perishes equally
as far as the soul is concerned; for it is impossible to imagine
that it still feels, from the moment when it is no longer in the
same conditions of existence, and no longer possesses the same
movements of existence in reference to the same organic system;
from the moment, in short, when the things which cover and
surround it are no longer such, that it retains in them the
same movements as before.
(Epicurus expresses the same ideas in other works, and adds
that the soul is composed of atoms of the most perfect lightness
and roundness; atoms wholly different from those of fire.
He distinguishes in it the irrational part which is diffused over
the whole body, from the rational part which has its seat in
the chest, as is proved by the emotions of fear and joy. He
adds that sleep is produced when the parts of the soul diffused
over the whole of the body concentre themselves, or when they
disperse and escape by the pores of the body; for particles
emanate from all bodies.)
“It must also be observed, that I use the word incorporeal
(ἀσώματος) in the usual acceptation of the word, to express
that which is in itself conceived as such. Now, nothing can
be conceived in itself as incorporeal except the vacuum; but
the vacuum cannot be either passive or active; it is only the
condition and the place of movement. Accordingly, they who
pretend that the soul is incorporeal, utter words destitute of
sense; for, if it had this character, it would not be able either
to do or to suffer anything; but, as it is, we see plainly enough
that it is liable to both these circumstances.
“Let us then apply all these reasonings to the affections and
sensations, recollecting the ideas which we laid down at the
beginning, and then we shall see clearly that these general
principles contain an exact solution of all the particular cases.
“As to forms, and hues, and magnitudes, and weight, and the
other qualities which one looks upon as attributes, whether it
be of every body, or of those bodies only which are visible and
perceived by the senses, this is the point of view under which
they ought to be considered: they are not particular substances,
having a peculiar existence of their own, for that
cannot be conceived; nor can one say any more that they have
no reality at all. They are not incorporeal substances inherent
in the body, nor are they parts of the body. But they constitute
by their union the eternal substance and the essence of
the entire body. We must not fancy, however, that the body
is composed of them, as an aggregate is formed of particles of
the smallest dimensions of atoms or magnitudes, whatever
they may be, smaller than the compound body itself; they
only constitute by their union, I repeat, the eternal substance
of the body. Each of these attributes has ideas and particular
perceptions which correspond to it; but they cannot be perceived
independently of the whole subject taken entirely; the
union of all these perceptions forms the idea of the body.
Bodies often possess other attributes which are not eternally
inherent in them, but which, nevertheless, cannot be ranged
among the incorporeal and invisible things. Accordingly, it is
sufficient to express the general idea of the movement of
transference to enable us to conceive in a moment certain
distinct qualities, and those combined beings, which, being
taken in their totality, receive the name of bodies; and the
necessary and eternal attributes without which the body cannot
be conceived.
“There are certain conceptions corresponding to these attributes;
but, nevertheless, they cannot be known abstractedly,
and independently of some subjects; and further, inasmuch
as they are not attributes necessarily inherent in the idea of a
body, one can only conceive them in the moment in which
they are visible; they are realities nevertheless; and one
must not refuse them being an existence merely because they
have neither the characteristic of the compound beings to
which we give the name of bodies, nor that of the eternal
attributes. We should be equally deceived if we were to
suppose that they have a separate and independent existence;
for that is true neither of them nor of the eternal attributes.
They are, as one sees plainly, accidents of the body; accidents
which do not of necessity make any part of its nature; which
cannot be considered as independent substances, but still to
each of which sensation gives the peculiar character under
which it appears to us.
“Another important question is that of time. Here we
cannot apply any more the method of examination to which
we submit other objects, which we study with reference to a
given subject; and which we refer to the preconceptions which
exist in ourselves. We must seize, by analogy, and going
round the whole circle of things comprised under this general
denomination of time—we must seize, I say—that essential
character which causes us to say that a time is long or short.
It is not necessary for that purpose to seek for any new forms
of expression as preferable to those which are in common use;
we may content ourselves with those by which time is usually
indicated. Nor need we, as certain philosophers do, affirm
any particular attribute of time, for that would be to suppose
that its essence is the same as that of this attribute. It is
sufficient too seek for the ingredients of which this particular
nature which we call time is composed, and for the means by
which it is measured. For this we have no need of demonstration;
a simple exposition is sufficient. It is, in fact,
evident, that we speak of time as composed of days and nights,
and parts of days and nights; passiveness and impassibility,
movement and repose, are equally comprised in time. In
short, it is evident that in connection with these different
states, we conceive a particular property to which we give the
name of time.
(Epicurus lays down the same principles in the second book
of his treatise on Nature, and in his great Abridgment.)
“It is from the infinite that the worlds are derived, and all
the finite aggregates which present numerous analogies with
the things which we observe under our own eyes. Each of
these objects, great and small, has been separated from the
infinite by a movement peculiar to itself. On the other hand,
all these bodies will be successively destroyed, some more, and
others less rapidly; some under the influence of one cause, and
others because of the agency of some other.
(It is evident, after this, that Epicurus regards the worlds
as perishable, since he admits that their parts are capable of
transformation. He also says in other places, that the earth
rests suspended in the air.)
“We must not believe that the worlds have of necessity all
one identical form.
(He says, in fact, in the twelfth book of his treatise on the
World, that the worlds differ from one another; some being
spherical, other elliptical, and others of other shapes.)
“Nevertheless, there are not worlds of every possible form
and shape.
“Let us also beware of thinking that animals are derived
from the infinite; for there is no one who can prove that the
germs from which animals are born, and plants, and all the
other objects which we contemplate, have been brought from the
exterior in such a world, and that this same world would not
have been able to produce them of itself. This remark applies
particularly to the earth.
“Again, we must admit that in many and various respects,
nature is both instructed and constrained by circumstances
themselves; and that reason subsequently makes perfect and
enriches with additional discoveries the things which it has
borrowed from nature; in some cases rapidly, and in others
more slowly. And in some cases according to periods and
times greater than those which proceed from the infinite; in
other cases according to those which are smaller. So, originally
it was only in virtue of express agreements that one gave
names to things. But men whose ideas and passions varied
according to their respective nations, formed these names of
their own accord, uttering divers sounds produced by each
passion, or by each idea, following the differences of the
situations and of the peoples. At a later period one established
in each nation, in a uniform manner, particular terms intended
to render the relations more easy, and language more concise.
Educated men introduced the notion of things not discoverable
by the senses, and appropriated words to them when
they found themselves under the necessity of uttering their
thoughts; after this, other men, guided in every point by
reason, interpreted these words in the same sense.
“As to the heavenly phænomena, such as the motion and
course of the stars, the eclipses, their rising and setting, and
all other appearances of the same kind, we must beware of
thinking that they are produced by any particular being which
has regulated, or whose business it is to regulate, for the
future, the order of the world, a being immortal and perfectly
happy; for the cares and anxieties, the benevolence and the
anger, far from being compatible with felicity, are, on the contrary,
the consequence of weakness, of fear, and of the want
which a thing has of something else. We must not fancy
either that these globes of fire, which roll on in space, enjoy
a perfect happiness, and give themselves, with reflection
and wisdom, the motions which they possess. But we must
respect the established notions on this subject, provided,
nevertheless, that they do not all contradict the respect due
to truth; for nothing is more calculated to trouble the soul
than this strife of contradictory notions and principles. We
must therefore admit that from the first movement impressed
on the heavenly bodies since the organization of the world
there is derived a sort of necessity which regulates their course
to this day.
“Let us be well assured that it is to physiology that it belongs
to determine the causes of the most elevated phænomena, and
that happiness consists, above all things, in the science of the
heavenly things and their nature, and in the knowledge of
analogous phænomena which may aid us in the comprehension
of the ethics. These heavenly phænomena admit of several
explanations; they have no reason of a necessary character,
and one may explain them in different manners. In a word,
they have no relation—a moment’s consideration will prove
this by itself—with those imperishable and happy natures
which admit of no division and of no confusion. As for the
theoretical knowledge of the rising and setting of the stars,
of the movement of the sun between the tropics, of the
eclipses, and all other similar phænomena, that is utterly
useless, as far as any influence upon happiness that it can
have. Moreover, those who, though possessed of this knowledge,
are ignorant of nature, and of the most probable causes
of the phænomena, are no more protected from fear than if
they were in the most complete ignorance; they even experience
the most lively fears, for the trouble, with which the
knowledge of which they are possessed inspires them, can find
no issue, and is not dissipated by a clear perception of the
reasons of these phænomena.
“As to us, we find many explanations of the motions of the
sun, of the rising and setting of the stars, of the eclipses and
similar phænomena, just as well as of the more particular
phænomena. And one must not think that this method of
explanation is not sufficient to procure happiness and tranquillity.
Let us content ourselves with examining how it is
that similar phænomena are brought about under our own eyes,
and let us apply these observations to the heavenly objects
and to everything which is not known but indirectly. Let us
despise those people who are unable to distinguish facts susceptible
of different explanations from others which can only
exist and be explained in one single way. Let us disdain those
men who do not know, by means of the different images which
result from distance, how to give an account of the different
appearances of things; who, in a word, are ignorant what are
the objects which can excite any trouble in us. If, then, we
know that such a phænomenon can be brought about in the
same manner as another given phænomenon of the same character
which does not inspire us with any apprehension; and
if, on the other hand, we know that it can take place in many
different manners, we shall not be more troubled at the sight
of it than if we knew the real cause of it.
“We must also recollect that that which principally contributes
to trouble the spirit of men is the persuasion which
they cherish that the stars are beings imperishable and perfectly
happy, and that then one’s thoughts and actions are in
contradiction to the will of these superior beings; they also,
being deluded by these fables, apprehend an eternity of evils,
they fear the insensibility of death, as that could affect them.
What do I say? It is not even belief, but inconsiderateness
and blindness which govern them in every thing, to such
a degree that, not calculating these fears, they are just as much
troubled as if they had really faith in these vain phantoms.
And the real freedom from this kind of trouble consists in
being emancipated from all these things, and in preserving
the recollection of all the principles which we have established,
especially of the most essential of them. Accordingly,
it is well to pay a scrupulous attention to existing phænomena
and to the sensations, to the general sensations for general
things, and to the particular sensations for particular things.
In a word, we must take note of this, the immediate evidence
with which each of these judicial faculties furnishes us; for, if
we attend to these points, namely, whence confusion and fear
arise, we shall divine the causes correctly, and we shall deliver
ourselves from those feelings, tracing back the heavenly phænomena
to their causes, and also all the others which present
themselves at every step, and inspire the common people with
extreme terror.
“This, Herodotus, is a kind of summary and abridgment
of the whole question of natural philosophy. So that, if this
reasoning be allowed to be valid, and be preserved carefully in
the memory, the man who allows himself to be influenced by
it, even though he may not descend to a profound study of its
details, will have a great superiority of character over other
men. He will personally discover a great number of truths
which I have myself set forth in my entire work; and these
truths being stored in his memory, will be a constant assistance
to him. By means of these principles, those who have descended
into the details, and have studied the question sufficiently,
will be able, in bringing in all their particular knowledge
to bear on the general subject, to run over without difficulty
almost the entire circle of the natural philosophy; those, on
the other hand, who are not yet arrived at perfection, and
who have not been able to hear me lecture on these subjects,
will be able in their minds to run over the main of the
essential notions, and to derive assistance from them for the
tranquillity and happiness of life.”
This then is his letter on physics.
XXV. About the heavenly bodies he writes thus:—
EPICURUS TO PYTHOCLES, WISHING HE MAY DO WELL.
“Cleon has brought me your letter, in which you continue
to evince towards me an affection worthy of the friendship
which I have for you. You devote all your care, you tell me, to
engraving in your memory those ideas which contribute to the
happiness of life; and you entreat me at the same time to
send you a simple abridgment and abstract of my ideas on
the heavenly phænomena, in order that you may without
difficulty preserve the recollection of them. For, say you,
what I have written on this subject in my other works is
difficult to recollect, even with continual study.
“I willingly yield to your desire, and I have good hope,
that in fulfilling what you ask, I shall be useful too to many
others, especially to those who are as yet novices in the real
knowledge of nature, and to those to whom the perplexities
and the ordinary affairs of life leave but little leisure. Be
careful then to seize on those precepts thoroughly, engrave
them deeply in your memory, and meditate on them with the
abridgment addressed to Herodotus, which I also send you.
“Know then, that it is with the knowledge of the heavenly
phænomena, both with those which are spoken of in contact
with one another, and of those which have a spontaneous existence,
as with every other science; it has no other aim but
that freedom from anxiety, and that calmness which is derived
from a firm belief.
“It is not good to desire what is impossible, and to endeavour
to enunciate a uniform theory about everything; accordingly,
we ought not here to adopt the method, which we have followed
in our researches into Ethics, or in the solution of
problems of natural philosophy. We there said, for instance,
that there are no other things, except bodies and the vacuum,
that the atoms are the principles of things, and so of the rest.
In a word, we gave a precise and simple explanation of every
fact, conformable to appearances.
“We cannot act in the same way with respect to the heavenly
phænomena: these productions may depend upon several
different causes, and we may give many different explanations on
this subject, equally agreeing with the impressions of the senses.
Besides, it is not here a question about reasoning on new principles,
and of laying down, à priori, rules for the interpretation
of nature; the only guides for us to follow are the
appearances themselves; for that which we have in view is
not a set of systems and vain opinions, but much rather a life
exempt from every kind of disquietude.
“The heavenly phænomena do not inspire those who give
different explanations of them, conformable with appearances,
instead of explaining them by hypothesis, with any alarm.
But if, abandoning hypothesis, one at the same time renounces
the attempt to explain them by means of analogies
founded on appearances, then one is placing one’s self altogether
at a distance from the science of nature, in order to
fall into fables.
“It is possible that the heavenly phænomena may present
some apparent characters which appear to assimilate them
to those phænomena which we see taking place around ourselves,
without there being any real analogy at the bottom.
For the heavenly phænomena may depend for their production
on many different causes; nevertheless, we must observe the
appearances presented by each, and we must distinguish the
different circumstances which attach to them, and which can
be explained in different manners by means of analogous
phænomena which arise under our eyes.
“The world is a collection of things embraced by the heaven,
containing the stars, the earth, and all visible objects. This
collection, separated from the infinite, is terminated by an
extremity, which is either rare, or dense, or revolving, or in a
state of repose, or of a round, or triangular, or of some shape
or other in fact, for it may be of any shape, the dissolution of
which must bring the destruction of everything which they
embrace. In fact, it can take place in every sort of way, since
there is not one of those things which are seen which testifies
against this world in which we cannot detect any extremity;
and that such worlds are infinite in number is easily seen, and
also that such a world can exist both in the world and in the
μετακόσμιον, as we call the space between the worlds, being a
huge space made up of plenum and vacuum, but not, as some
philosophers pretend, an immensity of space absolutely empty.
This production of a world may be explained thus: seeds
suitably appropriated to such an end may emanate either from
one or from several worlds, or from the space that separates
them; they flow towards a particular point where they become
collected together and organized; after that, other germs come
to unite them together in such a way as to form a durable
whole, a basis, a nucleus to which all successive additions
unite themselves.
“One must not content one’s self in this question with saying,
as one of the natural philosophers has done, that there is a
re-union of the elements, or a violent motion in the vacuum
under the influence of necessity, and that the body which is
thus produced increases until it comes to crash against some
other; for this doctrine is contrary to appearances.
“The sun, the moon, and the other stars, were originally
formed separately, and were afterwards comprehended in the
entire total of the world. All the other objects which our
world comprises, for instance, the earth and the sea, were also
formed spontaneously, and subsequently gained size by the
addition and violent movement of light substances, composed
of elements of fire and air, or even of these two principles at
once. This explanation, moreover, is in accordance with the
impressions of the senses.
“As to the magnitude of the sun and of the other stars, it is
as far as we are concerned, such as it appears to us to be.”
(This same doctrine is reproduced, and occurs again in the
eleventh book of his treatise on Nature; where he says, “If
the distance has made it lose its size, à fortiori, it would take
away its brilliancy; for colour has not, any more than size, the
property of traversing distance without alteration.”)
“But, considered by itself, the sun may be a little greater or
a little smaller than it appears; or it may be just such as it
looks; for that is exactly the case with the fires of common
occurrence among men, which are perceived by the senses at
a distance. Besides, all the difficulties on this subject will be
easily explained if one attends to the clear evidence of the
perceptions, as I have shown in my books about Nature.
“The rising and setting of the sun, of the moon, and of the
stars, may depend on the fact of their becoming lighted up,
and extinguished alternately, and in the order which we behold.
One may also give other reasons for this phænomenon, which
are not contradicted by any sensible appearances; accordingly,
one might explain them by the passage of the stars above and
below the earth, for the impressions of the senses agree also
with this supposition.
“As to their motion, one may make that depend on the
circular movement of the entire heaven. One may also suppose
that the stars move, while the heaven itself is immoveable;
for there is nothing to prevent the idea that originally,
before the formation of the world, they may have received, by
the appointment of fate, an impulse from east to west, and
that now their movement continues in consequence of their
heat, as the fire naturally proceeds onwards in order to seek
the aliment which suits it.
“The intertropical movements of the sun and moon may
depend, either on the obliquity impressed by fate on the heaven
at certain determined epochs, or on the resistance of the air,
or on the fact that these ignited bodies stand in need of being
nourished by a matter suitable to their nature, and that this
matter fails them; or finally, they may depend on the fact of
their having originally received an impulse which compels
them to move as they do describing a sort of spiral figure.
The sensible evidence does not in the least contradict these
different suppositions, and all those of the same kind which
one can form, having always a due regard to what is possible,
and bringing back each phænomenon to its analogous appearances
in sensible facts, without disquieting one’s self about the
miserable speculations of the astronomers.
“The evacuations and subsequent replenishings of the moon
may depend either on a conversion of this body, or on the
different forms which the air when in a fiery state can adopt,
or perhaps to the interposition of another body, or lastly, to
some one of the causes by which one gives account of the
analogous phænomena which pass under our eyes. Provided,
however, that one does not obstinately adopt an exclusive
mode of explanation; and that, for want of knowing what is
possible for a man to explain, and what is inaccessible to his
intelligence; one does not throw one’s self into interminable
speculations.
“It may also be possibly the case that the moon has a light
of her own, or that she reflects that of the sun. For we see
around us many objects which are luminous of themselves, and
many others which have only a borrowed light. In a word,
one will not be arrested by any of the celestial phænomena,
provided that one always recollects that there are many
explanations possible; that one examines the principles and
reasons which agree with this mode of explanation, and that
one does not proceed in accounting for the facts which do not
agree with this method, to suffer one’s self to be foolishly carried
away, and to propose a separate explanation for each phænomenon,
sometimes in one way, and sometimes in another.
“The appearance of a face in the orb of the moon, may
depend either on a displacement of its parts, or on the interposition
of some obstacle, or on any other cause capable of
accounting for such an appearance. For one must not neglect
to apply this same method to all the heavenly phænomena;
for, from the moment when one comes to any point of contradiction
to the evidence of the senses, it will be impossible to
possess perfect tranquillity and happiness.
“The eclipses of the sun and moon may depend either on
the fact that these stars extinguish themselves, a phænomenon
which we often see produced under our eyes, or on the
fact of other bodies, the earth, the heaven, or something else
of the same kind interposing, between them and us. Besides,
we must compare the different modes of explanation appropriate
to phænomena, and recollect that it is not impossible
that many causes may at one and the same time concur in
their production.
(He says the same thing in the twelfth book of his treatise
on Nature; and adds that the eclipses of the sun arise from
the fact that it penetrates into the shade of the moon, to quit
it again presently; and the eclipses of the moon from the fact
of its entering into the shade of the earth. We also find the
same doctrine asserted by Diogenes, the Epicurean, in the
first book of his Select Opinions.)
“The regular and periodical march of these phænomena has
nothing in it that ought to surprise us, if we only attend to
the analogous facts which take place under our eyes. Above
all things let us beware of making the Deity interpose here,
for that being we ought to suppose exempt from all occupation
and perfectly happy; otherwise we shall be only giving vain
explanations of the heavenly phænomena, as has happened
already to a crowd of authors. Not being able to recognize
what is really possible, they have fallen into vain theories, in
supposing that for all phænomena there was but one single
mode of production, and in rejecting all other explanations
which are founded on probability; they have adopted the
most unreasonable opinions, for want of placing in the front
the study of the heavenly phænomena, and of sensible facts,
which ought to serve to explain the first.
“The differences in the length of nights and days may arise
from the fact that the passage of the sun above the earth
is more or less rapid; and more or less slow, according to
the length of the regions which it has to pass through. Or,
again, to the fact that certain regions are passed through more
rapidly than others, as is seen to be the case by our own eyes,
in those things to which we can compare the heavenly phænomena.
As to those who on this point admit only one
explanation as possible, they put themselves in opposition to
facts, and lose sight of the bounds set to human knowledge.
“The prognostics which are derived from the stars may, like
those which we borrow from animals, arise from a simple
coincidence. They may also have other causes, for example,
some change in the air; for these two suppositions both
harmonize equally with facts; but it is impossible to distinguish
in what case one is to attribute them to the one cause or to
the other.
“The clouds may be formed either by the air condensed
under the pressure of the winds, or by the agency of atoms
set apart for that end, or by emanations from the earth and
waters, or by other causes. For there are a great number
which are all equally able to produce this effect. When the
clouds clash with one another, or undergo any transformation,
they produce showers; and the long rains are caused by the
motion of the clouds when moved from places suitable to them
through the air, when a more violent inundation than usual
takes place, from collections of some masses calculated to
produce these effects.
“Thunder possibly arises from the movement of the winds
revolving in the cavities of the clouds; of which we may see
an image in vessels in our own daily use. It may also arise
from the noise of fire acted upon by the wind in them, and
from the tearings and ruptures of the clouds when they have
received a sort of crystaline consistency. In a word, experience
drawn from our senses, teaches us that all these phænomena,
and that one in particular, may be produced in many
different manners.
“One may also assign different causes to the lightning;
either the shock and collision of the clouds produce a fiery
appearance, which is followed by lightning; or the lighting
up of the clouds by the winds, produces this luminous appearance;
or the mutual pressure of the clouds, or that of the
wind against them, disengages the lightning. Or, one might
say, that the interception of the light diffused from the stars,
arrested for a time in the bosom of the clouds, is driven from
them subsequently by their own movements, and by those of
the winds, and so escapes from their sides; that the lightning
is an extremely subtile light that evaporates from the
clouds; that the clouds which carry the thunder are collected
masses of fire; that the lightning arises from the motion of
the fire, or from the conflagration of the wind, in consequence
of the rapidity and continuousness of its motion. One may
also attribute the luminous appearance of lightning to the
rupture of the clouds under the action of the winds, or to the
fall of inflammable atoms. Lastly, one may easily find a
number of other explanations, if one applies to sensible facts,
in order to search out the analogies which they present to the
heavenly phænomena.
“Lightning precedes thunder, either because it is produced
at the same moment that the wind falls on the cloud, while
the noise is only heard at the instant when the wind has
penetrated into the bosom of the cloud; or, perhaps, the two
phænomena being simultaneous, the lightning arrives among
us more rapidly than the noise of the thunder-bolt, as is in
fact remarked in other cases when we see at a distance the
clash of two objects.
“The thunderbolt may be produced either by a violent condensation
of the winds, or by their rapid motion and conflagration.
It may arise from the fact of the winds meeting in
places which are too dense, in consequence of the accumulation
of clouds, and then a portion of the current detaches itself and
proceeds towards the lower situations; or else it may be caused
by the fire which is contained in the bosom of the clouds precipitating
itself downwards. As one may suppose that an
immense quantity of fire being accumulated in the clouds
dilates, violently bursting the substance which envelops it,
because the resistance of the centre hinders it from proceeding
further. This effect is especially produced in the neighbourhood
of high mountains; and, accordingly, they are very
frequently struck with the thunderbolts. In short, one may
give a number of explanations of the thunderbolt; but we
ought, above all things, to be on our guard against fables, and
this one will easily be, if one follows faithfully the sensible
phænomena in the explanation of these things, which are not
perceived, except indirectly.
“Hurricanes (πρηστῆρες) may be caused either by the presence
of a cloud, which a violent wind sets in motion and precipitates
with a spiral movement towards the lower regions, or by a
violent gust which bears a cloud into the neighbourhood of
some other current, or else by the mere agitation of the wind
by itself, when air is brought together from the higher regions
and compressed without being able to escape on either side, in
consequence of the resistance of the air which surrounds it;
when the hurricane descends towards the earth, then there
result whirlwinds in proportion to the rapidity of the wind
that has produced them; and this phænomenon extends over
the sea also.
“Earthquakes may arise from the wind penetrating into the
interior of the earth, or from the earth itself receiving incessantly
the addition of exterior particles, and being in
incessant motion as to its constituent atoms, being in consequence
disposed to a general vibration. That which permits
the wind to penetrate is the fact that falls take place in
the interior, or that the air being impressed by the winds
insinuates itself into the subterraneous caverns. The movement
which numberless falls and the re-action of the earth
communicate to the earth, when this motion meets bodies of
greater resistance and solidity, is sufficient to explain the
earthquakes. One might, however, give an account of them
in several other ways.
“Winds are caused, either by the successive and regular
addition of some foreign matter, or else by the re-union of
a great quantity of water; and the differences of the winds
may arise from the fact that some portions of this same matter
fall into the numerous cavities of the earth, and are divided
there.
“Hail is produced by an energetic condensation acting on
the ethereal particles which the cold embraces in every direction;
or, in consequence of a less violent condensation acting
however on aqueous particles, and accompanied by division, in
such a manner as to produce, at the same time, the re-union
of certain elements and of the collective masses; or by the
rupture of some dense and compact mass which would explain
at the same time, the numerousness of the particles and their
individual hardness. As to the spherical form of the hail, one
may easily account for that by admitting that the shocks
which it receives in every direction make all the angles
disappear, or else that at the moment when the different
fragments are formed, each of them is equally embraced on all
sides by aqueous or ethereal particles.
“Snow may be produced by a light vapour full of moisture
which the clouds allow to escape by passages intended for that
end, when they are pressed, in a corresponding manner, by
other clouds, and set in motion by the wind. Subsequently,
these vapours become condensed in their progress under the
action of the cold which surrounds the clouds in the lower
regions. It may also be the case that this phænomenon is
produced by clouds of a slight density as they become condensed.
In this case the snow which escapes from the clouds
would be the result of the contact, or approximation of the
aqueous particles, which in a still more condensed state produce
hail. This effect is most especially produced in the air. Snow,
again, may result from the collection of clouds previously condensed
and solidified; or from a whole army of other causes.
“Dew proceeds from a re-union of particles contained in the
air calculated to produce this moist substance. These particles
may be also brought from places which are moist or covered
with water (for in those places, above all others, it is that
dew is abundant). These then re-unite, again resume their
aqueous form, and fall down. The same phænomenon takes
place in other cases before our own eyes under many analogies.
“Hoar-frost is dew congealed by the influence of the cold
air that surrounds it.
“Ice is formed either by the detrition of round atoms contained
in the water, and the re-union at scalene and acute
angles of the atoms which exist in the water, or by an addition
from without of these latter particles, which penetrating into
the water, solidify it by driving away an equal amount of round
atoms.
“The rainbow may be produced by the reflection of the solar
rays on the moist air; or it may arise from a particular property
of light and air, in virtue of which these particular
appearances of colour are formed, either because the shades
which we perceive result directly from this property, or because,
on the contrary, it only produces one single shade, which,
reflecting itself on the nearest portions of the air, communicates
to them the tints which we observe. As to the circular
form of the rainbow, that depends either on the fact of the
sight perceiving an equal distance in every direction, or the
fact of the atoms taking this form when re-uniting in the air;
or it may be caused by its detaching from the air which moves
towards the moon, certain atoms which, being re-united in the
clouds, give rise to this circular appearance.
“The lunar halo arises from the fact of the air, which moves
towards the moon from all quarters, uniformly intercepting the
rays emitted by this star, in such a way as to form around it
a sort of circular cloud which partially veils it. It may also
arise from the fact of the moon uniformly rejecting from all
quarters, the air which surrounds it, in such a manner as to
produce this circular and opaque covering. And perhaps this
opaqueness may be caused by some particles which some
current brings from without; perhaps also, the heat communicates
to the moon the property of emitting by the pores in
its surface, the particles by which this effect is produced.
“Comets arise either from the fact, that in the circumstances
already stated, there are partial conflagrations in certain points
of the heaven; or, that at certain periods, the heaven has
above our heads a particular movement which causes them to
appear. It may also be the case, that being themselves
endowed with a peculiar movement, they advance at the end
of certain periods of time, and in consequence of particular
circumstances, towards the places which we inhabit. The
opposite reasons explain their disappearance.
“Certain stars return to the same point in accomplishing
their revolutions; and this arises, not only as has been sometimes
believed, from the fact of the pole of the world, around
which they move, being immoveable, but also from the fact
that the gyrations of the air which surrounds them, hinder
them from deviations like the wandering stars. Perhaps also,
this may be caused by the fact, that except in the route in
which they move, and in which we perceive them, they do not
find any material suitable to their nature. One may also
explain this phænomenon in many other manners, reasoning
according to sensible facts; thus, it is possible that certain
stars may be wandering because that is the nature of their
movements, and, for the same reason, others may be immoveable.
It is also possible, that the same necessity which has
originally given them their circular movement, may have
compelled some to follow their orbit regularly, and have
subjected others to an irregular progress; we may also suppose
that the uniform character of the centre which certain stars
traverse favour their regular march, and their return to a certain;
and that in the case of others, on the contrary, the differences
of the centre produce the changes which we observe. Besides,
to assign one single cause to all these phænomena, when the
experience of our senses suggests us several, is folly. It is
the conduct of ignorant astronomers covetous of a vain knowledge,
who, assigning imaginary causes to facts, wish to leave
wholly to the Deity the care of the government of the universe.
“Some stars appear to be left behind by others in their
progress; this arises either from the fact of their having a
slower motion, though traversing the same circle; or, because,
though they are drawn on by the same propelling power, they
have, nevertheless, a movement proper to themselves in a
contrary direction; or it may be caused by the fact that,
though all are placed in the same sphere of movement, still
some have more space to traverse, and others less. To give
one uniform and positive explanation of all these facts, is not
consistent with the conduct of any people but those who love
to flash prodigies in the eyes of the multitude.
“Falling stars may be particles detached from the stars, or
fragments resulting from their collision; they may also be
produced by the fall of substances which are set on fire by the
action of the wind; by the re-union of inflammable atoms
which are made to come together so as to produce this effect
by a sort of reciprocal attraction; or else by the movement
which is produced in consequence of the re-union of atoms in
the very place where they meet. It may also happen that
the light vapours re-unite and become condensed under the
form of clouds, that they then take fire in consequence of their
rotatory motion, and that, bursting the obstacles which surround
them, they proceed towards the places whither the force by
which they are animated drags them. In short, this phænomenon
also may admit of a great number of explanations.
“The presages which are drawn from certain animals arise
from a fortuitous concourse of circumstances; for there is no
necessary connection between certain animals and winter. They
do not produce it; nor is there any divine nature sitting
aloft watching the exits of these animals, and then accomplishing
signs of this kind. Nor can such folly as this occur
to any being who is even moderately comfortable, much less
to one which is possessed of perfect happiness.
“Imprint all these precepts in your memory, O Pythocles,
and so you will easily escape fables, and it will be easy for you to
discover other truths analogous to these. Above all, apply yourself
to the study of general principles, of the infinite, and of questions
of this kind, and to the investigation of the different criteria
and of the passions, and to the study of the chief good, with a
view to which we prosecute all our researches. When these questions
are once resolved, all particular difficulties will be made
plain to you. As to those who will not apply themselves to
these principles, they will neither be able to give a good explanation
of these same questions, nor to reach that end to
which all our researches tend.”
XXVI. Such are his sentiments on the heavenly phænomena.
But concerning the rules of life, and how we ought to
choose some things, and avoid others, he writes thus. But
first of all, let us go through the opinions which he held, and
his disciples held about the wise man.
He said that injuries existed among men, either in consequence
of hatred, or of envy, or of contempt, all which the
wise man overcomes by reason. Also, that a man who has
once been wise can never receive the contrary disposition, nor
can he of his own accord invent such a state of things as that
he should be subjected to the dominion of the passions; nor
can he hinder himself in his progress towards wisdom. That
the wise man, however, cannot exist in every state of body,
nor in every nation. That even if the wise man were to be
put to the torture, he would still be happy. That the wise
man will only feel gratitude to his friends, but to them equally
whether they are present or absent. Nor will he groan and
howl when he is put to the torture. Nor will he marry a wife
whom the laws forbid, as Diogenes says, in his epitome of the
Ethical Maxims of Epicurus. He will punish his servants,
but also pity them, and show indulgence to any that are
virtuous. They do not think that the wise man will ever be
in love, nor that he will be anxious about his burial, nor that
love is a passion inspired by the Gods, as Diogenes says in
his twelfth book. They also assert that he will be indifferent
to the study of oratory. Marriage, say they, is never any good
to a man, and we must be quite content if it does no harm;
and the wise man will never marry or beget children, as
Epicurus himself lays it down, in his Doubts and in his
treatises on Nature. Still, under certain circumstances of life,
he will forsake these rules and marry. Nor will he ever
indulge in drunkenness, says Epicurus, in his Banquet, nor
will he entangle himself in affairs of state (as he says in his
first book on Lives). Nor will he become a tyrant. Nor will
he become a Cynic (as he says in his second book about Lives).
Nor a beggar. And even, though he should lose his eyes, he
will still partake of life (as he says in the same book).
The wise man will be subject to grief, as Diogenes says, in
the fifth book of his Select Opinions; he will also not object
to go to law. He will leave books and memorials of himself
behind him, but he will not be fond of frequenting assemblies.
He will take care of his property, and provide for the future.
He will like being in the country, he will resist fortune, and
will grieve none of his friends. He will show a regard for a fair
reputation to such an extent as to avoid being despised; and
he will find more pleasure than other men in speculations.
All faults are not equal. Health is good for some people,
but a matter of indifference to others. Courage is a quality
which does not exist by nature, but which is engendered by a
consideration of what is suitable. Friendship is caused by
one’s wants; but it must be begun on our side. For we sow
the earth; and friendship arises from a community of, and
participation in, pleasures. Happiness must be understood in
two senses; the highest happiness, such as is that of God,
which admits of no increase; and another kind, which admits
of the addition or abstraction of pleasures. The wise man may
raise statues if it suits his inclination, if it does not it does
not signify. The wise man is the only person who can converse
correctly about music and poetry; and he can realise
poems, but not become a poet.
It is possible for one wise man to be wiser than another.
The wise man will also, if he is in need, earn money, but only
by his wisdom; he will propitiate an absolute ruler when
occasion requires, and will humour him for the sake of correcting
his habits; he will have a school, but not on such a
system as to draw a crowd about him; he will also recite in a
multitude, but that will be against his inclination; he will
pronounce dogmas, and will express no doubts; he will be the
same man asleep and awake; and he will be willing even to
die for a friend.
These are the Epicurean doctrines.
XXVII. We must now proceed to his letter:—
EPICURUS TO MENŒCEUS, GREETING
“Let no one delay to study philosophy while he is young,
and when he is old let him not become weary of the study;
for no man can ever find the time unsuitable or too late to
study the health of his soul. And he who asserts either that
it is not yet time to philosophize, or that the hour is passed,
is like a man who should say that the time is not yet come to
be happy, or that it is too late. So that both young and old
should study philosophy, the one in order that, when he is old,
he may be young in good things through the pleasing recollection
of the past, and the other in order that he may be at the
same time both young and old, in consequence of his absence
of fear for the future.
“It is right then for a man to consider the things which produce
happiness, since, if happiness is present, we have everything,
and when it is absent, we do everything with a view to
possess it. Now, what I have constantly recommended to you,
these things I would have you do and practise, considering
them to be the elements of living well. First of all, believe
that God is a being incorruptible and happy, as the common
opinion of the world about God dictates; and attach to your
idea of him nothing which is inconsistent with incorruptibility
or with happiness; and think that he is invested with everything
which is able to preserve to him this happiness, in
conjunction with incorruptibility. For there are Gods; for
our knowledge of them is indistinct. But they are not of the
character which people in general attribute to them; for they
do not pay a respect to them which accords with the ideas that
they entertain of them. And that man is not impious who
discards the Gods believed in by the many, but he who applies
to the Gods the opinions entertained of them by the many.
For the assertions of the many about the Gods are not anticipations
(προλήψεις), but false opinions (ὑπολήψεις). And in
consequence of these, the greatest evils which befall wicked
men, and the benefits which are conferred on the good, are all
attributed to the Gods; for they connect all their ideas of
them with a comparison of human virtues, and everything
which is different from human qualities, they regard as incompatible
with the divine nature.
“Accustom yourself also to think death a matter with which
we are not at all concerned, since all good and all evil is in
sensation, and since death is only the privation of sensation.
On which account, the correct knowledge of the fact that
death is no concern of ours, makes the mortality of life pleasant
to us, inasmuch as it sets forth no illimitable time, but relieves
us for the longing for immortality. For there is nothing
terrible in living to a man who rightly comprehends that there
is nothing terrible in ceasing to live; so that he was a silly
man who said that he feared death, not because it would grieve
him when it was present, but because it did grieve him while
it was future. For it is very absurd that that which does not
distress a man when it is present, should afflict him when only
expected. Therefore, the most formidable of all evils, death,
is nothing to us, since, when we exist, death is not present to
us; and when death is present, then we have no existence.
It is no concern then either of the living or of the dead; since
to the one it has no existence, and the other class has no
existence itself. But people in general, at times flee from
death as the greatest of evils, and at times wish for it as a rest
from the evils in life. Nor is the not living a thing feared,
since living is not connected with it: nor does the wise man
think not living an evil; but, just as he chooses food, not
preferring that which is most abundant, but that which is
nicest; so too, he enjoys time, not measuring it as to whether
it is of the greatest length, but as to whether it is most agreeable.
And he who enjoins a young man to live well, and an
old man to die well, is a simpleton, not only because of the
constantly delightful nature of life, but also because the care
to live well is identical with the care to die well. And he
was still more wrong who said:—
“’Tis well to taste of life, and then when born
To pass with quickness to the shades below.
“For if this really was his opinion why did he not quit life?
for it was easily in his power to do so, if it really was his
belief. But if he was joking, then he was talking foolishly in
a case where it ought not to be allowed; and, we must recollect,
that the future is not our own, nor, on the other hand, is it
wholly not our own, I mean so that we can never altogether
await it with a feeling of certainty that it will be, nor altogether
despair of it as what will never be. And we must consider
that some of the passions are natural, and some empty;
and of the natural ones some are necessary, and some merely
natural. And of the necessary ones some are necessary to
happiness, and others, with regard to the exemption of the
body, from trouble; and others with respect to living itself; for
a correct theory, with regard to these things, can refer all
choice and avoidance to the health of the body and the freedom
from disquietude of the soul. Since this is the end of living
happily; for it is for the sake of this that we do everything,
wishing to avoid grief and fear; and when once this is the
case, with respect to us, then the storm of the soul is, as I may
say, put an end to; since the animal is unable to go as if to
something deficient, and to seek something different from that
by which the good of the soul and body will be perfected.
“For then we have need of pleasure when we grieve, because
pleasure is not present; but when we do not grieve, then we
have no need of pleasure; and on this account, we affirm, that
pleasure is the beginning and end of living happily; for we
have recognized this as the first good, being connate with
us; and with reference to it, it is that we begin every choice
and avoidance; and to this we come as if we judged of all good
by passion as the standard; and, since this is the first good
and connate with us, on this account we do not choose every
pleasure, but at times we pass over many pleasures when any
difficulty is likely to ensue from them; and we think many
pains better than pleasures, when a greater pleasure follows
them, if we endure the pain for a time.
“Every pleasure is therefore a good on account of its own nature,
but it does not follow that every pleasure is worthy of being
chosen; just as every pain is an evil, and yet every pain must
not be avoided. But it is right to estimate all these things by
the measurement and view of what is suitable and unsuitable;
for at times we may feel the good as an evil, and at times, on
the contrary, we may feel the evil as good. And, we think,
contentment a great good, not in order that we may never have
but a little, but in order that, if we have not much, we may
make use of a little, being genuinely persuaded that those
men enjoy luxury most completely who are the best able to do
without it; and that everything which is natural is easily
provided, and what is useless is not easily procured. And simple
flavours give as much pleasure as costly fare, when everything
that can give pain, and every feeling of want, is removed; and
corn and water give the most extreme pleasure when any one
in need eats them. To accustom one’s self, therefore, to simple
and inexpensive habits is a great ingredient in the perfecting
of health, and makes a man free from hesitation with respect
to the necessary uses of life. And when we, on certain occasions,
fall in with more sumptuous fare, it makes us in a
better disposition towards it, and renders us fearless with
respect to fortune. When, therefore, we say that pleasure is
a chief good, we are not speaking of the pleasures of the
debauched man, or those which lie in sensual enjoyment, as
some think who are ignorant, and who do not entertain our
opinions, or else interpret them perversely; but we mean the
freedom of the body from pain, and of the soul from confusion.
For it is not continued drinkings and revels, or the enjoyment
of female society, or feasts of fish and other such things, as a
costly table supplies, that make life pleasant, but sober contemplation,
which examines into the reasons for all choice
and avoidance, and which puts to flight the vain opinions
from which the greater part of the confusion arises which
troubles the soul.
“Now, the beginning and the greatest good of all these
things is prudence, on which account prudence is something
more valuable than even philosophy, inasmuch as all the other
virtues spring from it, teaching us that it is not possible to
live pleasantly unless one also lives prudently, and honourably,
and justly; and that one cannot live prudently, and honestly,
and justly, without living pleasantly; for the virtues are
connate with living agreeably, and living agreeably is inseparable
from the virtues. Since, who can you think better
than that man who has holy opinions respecting the Gods, and
who is utterly fearless with respect to death, and who has
properly contemplated the end of nature, and who comprehends
that the chief good is easily perfected and easily provided;
and the greatest evil lasts but a short period, and
causes but brief pain. And who has no belief in necessity,
which is set up by some as the mistress of all things, but he
refers some things to fortune, some to ourselves, because necessity
is an irresponsible power, and because he sees that
fortune is unstable, while our own will is free; and this freedom
constitutes, in our case, a responsibility which makes us encounter
blame and praise. Since it would be better to follow
the fables about the Gods than to be a slave to the fate of the
natural philosopher; for the fables which are told give us a
sketch, as if we could avert the wrath of God by paying him
honour; but the other presents us with necessity who is
inexorable.
“And he, not thinking fortune a goddess, as the generality
esteem her (for nothing is done at random by a God), nor a
cause which no man can rely on, for he thinks that good or
evil is not given by her to men so as to make them live happily,
but that the principles of great goods or great evils are supplied
by her; thinking it better to be unfortunate in accordance
with reason, than to be fortunate irrationally; for that those
actions which are judged to be the best, are rightly done in
consequence of reason.
“Do you then study these precepts, and those which are akin
to them, by all means day and night, pondering on them by
yourself, and discussing them with any one like yourself, and
then you will never be disturbed by either sleeping or waking
fancies, but you will live like a God among men; for a man
living amid immortal Gods, is in no respect like a mortal
being.”
In other works, he discards divination; and also in his
Little Epitome. And he says divination has no existence;
but, if it has any, still we should think that what happens
according to it is nothing to us.
These are his sentiments about the things which concern
the life of man, and he has discussed them at greater length
elsewhere.
XXVIII. Now, he differs with the Cyrenaics about pleasure.
For they do not admit that to be pleasure which exists as a
condition, but place it wholly in motion. He, however, admits
both kinds to be pleasure, namely, that of the soul, and that
of the body, as he says in his treatise on Choice and Avoidance;
and also in his work on the Chief Good; and in the
first book of his treatise on Lives, and in his Letter against
the Mitylenian Philosophers. And in the same spirit, Diogenes,
in the seventeenth book of his Select Discourses, and
Metrodorus, in his Timocrates, speak thus. “But when
pleasure is understood, I mean both that which exists in
motion, and that which is a state.…” And Epicurus,
in his treatise on Choice, speaks thus: “Now, freedom from
disquietude, and freedom from pain, are states of pleasure;
but joy and cheerfulness are beheld in motion and energy.”
XXIX. For they make out the pains of the body to be
worse than those of the mind; accordingly, those who do
wrong, are punished in the body. But he considers the pains
of the soul the worst; for that the flesh is only sensible to
present affliction, but the soul feels the past, the present, and
the future. Therefore, in the same manner, he contends that
the pleasures of the soul are greater than those of the body;
and he uses as a proof that pleasure is the chief good, the fact
that all animals from the moment of their birth are delighted
with pleasure, and are offended with pain by their natural
instinct, and without the employment of reason. Therefore,
too, we, of our own inclination, flee from pain; so that
Hercules, when devoured by his poisoned tunic, cries out:—
Shouting and groaning, and the rocks around
Re-echoed his sad wails, the mountain heights
Of Locrian lands, and sad Eubœa’s hills.
XXX. And we choose the virtues for the sake of pleasure,
and not on their own account; just as we seek the skill of
the physician for the sake of health, as Diogenes says, in the
twentieth book of his Select Discourses, where he also calls
virtue a way of passing one’s life (διαγωγή). But Epicurus
says, that virtue alone is inseparable from pleasure, but that
every thing else may be separated from it as mortal.
XXXI. Let us, however, now add the finishing stroke, as
one may say, to this whole treatise, and to the life of the
philosopher; giving some of his fundamental maxims, and
closing the whole work with them, taking that for our end
which is the beginning of happiness.
. “That which is happy and imperishable, neither has
trouble itself, nor does it cause it to anything; so that it is
not subject to the feelings of either anger or gratitude; for
these feelings only exist in what is weak.
(In other passages he says that the Gods are speculated on
by reason, some existing according to number, and others
according to some similarity of form, arising from the continual
flowing on of similar images, perfected for this very
purpose in human form.)
. “Death is nothing to us; for that which is dissolved is
devoid of sensation, and that which is devoid of sensation is
nothing to us.
. “The limit of the greatness of the pleasures is the
removal of everything which can give pain. And where
pleasure is, as long as it lasts, that which gives pain, or that
which feels pain, or both of them, are absent.
. “Pain does not abide continuously in the flesh, but in
its extremity it is present only a very short time. That pain
which only just exceeds the pleasure in the flesh, does not
last many days. But long diseases have in them more that is
pleasant than painful to the flesh.
. “It is not possible to live pleasantly without living
prudently, and honourably, and justly; nor to live prudently,
and honourably, and justly, without living pleasantly. But he
to whom it does not happen to live prudently, honourably, and
justly, cannot possibly live pleasantly.
. “For the sake of feeling confidence and security with
regard to men, and not with reference to the nature of government
and kingly power being a good, some men have wished
to be eminent and powerful, in order that others might attain
this feeling by their means; thinking that so they would secure
safety as far as men are concerned. So that, if the life of
such men is safe, they have attained to the nature of good;
but if it is not safe, then they have failed in obtaining that for
the sake of which they originally desired power according to
the order of nature.
. “No pleasure is intrinsically bad: but the efficient
causes of some pleasures bring with them a great many perturbations
of pleasure.
. “If every pleasure were condensed, if one may so say,
and if each lasted long, and affected the whole body, or the
essential parts of it, then there would be no difference between
one pleasure and another.
. “If those things which make the pleasures of debauched
men, put an end to the fears of the mind, and to those which
arise about the heavenly bodies, and death, and pain; and if
they taught us what ought to be the limit of our desires, we
should have no pretence for blaming those who wholly devote
themselves to pleasure, and who never feel any pain or grief
(which is the chief evil) from any quarter.
. “If apprehensions relating to the heavenly bodies did
not disturb us, and if the terrors of death have no concern
with us, and if we had the courage to contemplate the boundaries
of pain and of the desires, we should have no need of
physiological studies.
. “It would not be possible for a person to banish all
fear about those things which are called most essential, unless
he knew what is the nature of the universe, or if he had any
idea that the fables told about it could be true; and therefore,
it is, that a person cannot enjoy unmixed pleasure without
physiological knowledge.
. “It would be no good for a man to secure himself
safety as far as men are concerned, while in a state of apprehension
as to all the heavenly bodies, and those under the
earth, and in short, all those in the infinite.
. “Irresistible power and great wealth may, up to a certain
point, give us security as far as men are concerned; but the
security of men in general depends upon the tranquillity of
their souls, and their freedom from ambition.
. “The riches of nature are defined and easily procurable;
but vain desires are insatiable.
. “The wise man is but little favoured by fortune; but
his reason procures him the greatest and most valuable goods,
and these he does enjoy, and will enjoy the whole of his life.
. “The just man is the freest of all men from disquietude;
but the unjust man is a perpetual prey to it.
. “Pleasure in the flesh is not increased, when once the
pain arising from want is removed; it is only diversified.
. “The most perfect happiness of the soul depends on
these reflections, and on opinions of a similar character on all
those questions which cause the greatest alarm to the mind.
. “Infinite and finite time both have equal pleasure,
if any one measures its limits by reason.
. “If the flesh could experience boundless pleasure, it
would want to dispose of eternity.
. “But reason, enabling us to conceive the end and
dissolution of the body, and liberating us from the fears
relative to eternity, procures for us all the happiness of which
life is capable, so completely that we have no further occasion
to include eternity in our desires. In this disposition of
mind, man is happy even when his troubles engage him to
quit life; and to die thus, is for him only to interrupt a life
of happiness.
. “He who is acquainted with the limits of life knows,
that that which removes the pain which arises from want, and
which makes the whole of life perfect, is easily procurable; so
that he has no need of those things which can only be attained
with trouble.
. “But as to the subsisting end, we ought to consider it
with all the clearness and evidence which we refer to whatever
we think and believe; otherwise, all things will be full of
confusion and uncertainty of judgment.
. “If you resist all the senses, you will not even have
anything left to which you can refer, or by which you may be
able to judge of the falsehood of the senses which you condemn.
. “If you simply discard one sense, and do not distinguish
between the different elements of the judgment, so as to know
on the one hand, the induction which goes beyond the actual
sensation, or, on the other, the actual and immediate notion;
the affections, and all the conceptions of the mind which lean
directly on the sensible representation, you will be imputing
trouble into the other sense, and destroying in that quarter
every species of criterion.
. “If you allow equal authority to the ideas, which,
being only inductive, require to be verified, and to those
which bear about them an immediate certainty, you will not
escape error; for you will be confounding doubtful opinions
with those which are not doubtful, and true judgments with
those of a different character.
. “If, on every occasion, we do not refer every one of
our actions to the chief end of nature, if we turn aside from
that to seek or avoid some other object, there will be a want
of agreement between our words and our actions.
. “Of all the things which wisdom provides for the happiness
of the whole life, by far the most important is the
acquisition of friendship.
. “The same opinion encourages man to trust that no
evil will be everlasting, or even of long duration; as it sees
that, in the space of life allotted to us, the protection of friendship
is most sure and trustworthy.
. “Of the desires, some are natural and necessary, some
natural, but not necessary, and some are neither natural nor
necessary, but owe their existence to vain opinions.”
(Epicurus thinks that those are natural and necessary which
put an end to pains, as drink when one is thirsty; and that
those are natural but not necessary which only diversify pleasure,
but do not remove pain, such as expensive food; and
that these are neither natural nor necessary, which are such
as crowns, or the erection of statues.)
. “Those desires which do not lead to pain, if they are not
satisfied, are not necessary. It is easy to impose silence on
them when they appear difficult to gratify, or likely to produce
injury.
. “When the natural desires, the failing to satisfy which
is, nevertheless, not painful, are violent and obstinate, it is a
proof that there is an admixture of vain opinion in them; for
then energy does not arise from their own nature, but from the
vain opinions of men.
. “Natural justice is a covenant of what is suitable, leading
men to avoid injuring one another, and being injured.
. “Those animals which are unable to enter into an argument
of this nature, or to guard against doing or sustaining
mutual injury, have no such thing as justice or injustice. And
the case is the same with those nations, the members of which
are either unwilling or unable to enter into a covenant to
respect their mutual interests.
. “Justice has no independent existence; it results from
mutual contracts, and establishes itself wherever there is a
mutual engagement to guard against doing or sustaining mutual
injury.
. “Injustice is not intrinsically bad; it has this character
only because there is joined with it a fear of not escaping those
who are appointed to punish actions marked with that character.
. “It is not possible for a man who secretly does anything
in contravention of the agreement which men have made with
one another, to guard against doing, or sustaining mutual
injury, to believe that he shall always escape notice, even if
he have escaped notice already ten thousand times; for, till
his death, it is uncertain whether he will not be detected.
. “In a general point of view, justice is the same thing to
every one; for there is something advantageous in mutual
society. Nevertheless, the difference of place, and divers other
circumstances, make justice vary.
. “From the moment that a thing declared just by the
law is generally recognized as useful for the mutual relations
of men, it becomes really just, whether it is universally regarded
as such or not.
. “But if, on the contrary, a thing established by law is
not really useful for the social relations, then it is not just;
and if that which was just, inasmuch as it was useful, loses this
character, after having been for some time considered so, it is
not less true that, during that time, it was really just, at least
for those who do not perplex themselves about vain words, but
who prefer, in every case, examining and judging for themselves.
. “When, without any fresh circumstances arising, a
thing which has been declared just in practice does not agree
with the impressions of reason, that is a proof that the thing
was not really just. In the same way, when in consequence
of new circumstances, a thing which has been pronounced just
does not any longer appear to agree with utility, the thing
which was just, inasmuch as it was useful to the social relations
and intercourse of mankind, ceases to be just the moment
when it ceases to be useful.
. “He who desires to live tranquilly without having any
thing to fear from other men, ought to make himself friends;
those whom he cannot make friends of, he should, at least,
avoid rendering enemies; and if that is not in his power, he
should, as far as possible, avoid all intercourse with them, and
keep them aloof, as far as it is for his interest to do so.
. “The happiest men are they who have arrived at the
point of having nothing to fear from those who surround them.
Such men live with one another most agreeably, having the
firmest grounds of confidence in one another, enjoying the advantages
of friendship in all their fulness, and not lamenting,
as a pitiable circumstance, the premature death of their
friends.”
|